VI INDUCTIVE
PROOF AND PERODICITY
29 How far is
a proof by induction a proof of a proposition?
‘If a proof of induction is a proof of a + (b + c)
= (a + b) + c, we must be able to say: the calculation gives the result that a
+ (b + c) = (a + b) + c (and no other result).
In that case the general method of calculating it
must be already known, and we must be able to work out a + (b + c) straight off
in the way we work out 25 x 16. So first there is a general rule taught for
working out all such problems, and later the particular cases are worked out. –
But what is the general method of working out here? It must be based on general
rules for signs (– say the associative law –)’
so induction is irrelevant to proof – yes
as for ‘inductive proof’ – it can only be a suggestion of proof – a speculation
or if inductive argument is regarded by
practitioners – mathematicians – as
being a form of proof – so be it –
but any such move – is I would suggest
unconventional and a departure from
standard mathematical thinking and practice –
and it’s hard to see what value there would in
calling suggestion and any argument based on it ‘proof’
‘If I negate a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c it only
makes sense if I mean to say something like: a + (b + c) isn’t (a + b) + c isn’t
(a +b) + c, but (a + 2b) + c. For the question is: In what space do I negate the proposition? If
I mark it off and exclude it, what do I exclude it from?
To check 25 x 25 = 625 I work out 25 x 25 until I
get the right hand result: - can I work out a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c, and get
the result (a + b) + c? Whether it is provable or not depends on whether we
treat it as calculable or not. For if the proposition is a rule, a paradigm,
which every proposition has to follow, then it makes more sense to talk of
working out the equation, than to talk of working out a definition.’
negation –
at best a proposal not to proceed with –
and you make such a proposal in whatever space your
in –
it’s an argument not to accept what has been proposed –
which in an argumentative context may well have
some value –
however in general – what we deal with in life and
mathematics is what is proposed – what is put –
you can of course – put an alternative – and by
implication ‘negate’ – what has been proposed –
but this is just a matter of deciding which way you
will go –
and that is the issue – where you will go – what
you propose
not where you won’t go – and not propose
‘can I work out a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c, and get
the result (a + b) + c?’ –
yes – if it has a calculus – and a recognisable /
usable system of rules –
which is to say – if it is a game – and not just a
string of symbols that has the form of a
game
as a definition it can only make sense in a
propositional context –
and as a rule it will only make sense in a game – a
rule structured propositional context
‘What makes the calculation possible is the system
to which the proposition belongs; and that also determines what miscalculation
can be made in the working out. E.g.
(a + b) 2, is a2, + 2ab + b2, and not a2, + ab + b2,; but (a + b) 2, = - 4 is not a possible
miscalculation in this system.’
a miscalculation – is – relative to the system – of
calculation – void –
it is not a
calculation
‘I might also say very roughly (see other remarks):
“25 x 64 = 160, 64 x 25 = 160; that proves that a x b = b x a” (this way of
speaking need not be absurd or
incorrect; you only have to interpret it correctly). The conclusion can be
correctly drawn from that; so in one sense a.b = b.a can be proved.
And I want to say: it is only in the sense in which you can tell working out such an example
a proof of the algebraic proposition that the proof by induction is a proof of
the proposition. Only to that extent is it a check of the algebraic
proposition. (It is a check of its structure, not its generality).’
a.b = b.a can be ‘proved’ – only in terms of a
substitution rules
induction – may lead
you to the rules –
may suggest the rules – may suggest the game –
it is no proof
‘(Philosophy does not examine the calculi of
mathematics, but only what mathematicians say about these calculi.)’
philosophers speculate on what makes mathematics –
mathematics –
what mathematicians say about mathematics – is just
one place for philosophers to start
30 Recursive
proof and the concept of proposition. Is proof a proof that a proposition is
true and it’s contradictory false?
‘Is the recursive proof of
a + (b + c)
= (a + b) + c …A
an answer to a question? If so, what question? Is
it a proof that an assertion is true and its contradictory false?’
a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c …A
is an example of the recursive game –
that is a game where the propositional action that recurs indefinitely
or until a specified condition is met –
is it an answer to a question?
no
is it a proof that an assertion is true and its
contradictory false?
recurrence of a propositional action – is just that
– recurrence –
a form of repetition
proof is an argument –
if recurrence is presented as an argument – it is a
rhetorical argument
is its contradictory false?
no –
its contradictory is another recursive game
‘What Skolem calls a recursive proof of A can be
written thus;
a + (b +1) =
(a + b) +1
a + (b + (c = 1)) = a ((b + c) + 1) = (a + (b + c))
+ 1 } B
(a + b) + (c + 1) = ((a + b) + c) + 1
If three equations of the form µ, b g are proved,
we say “the equation D is proved for all cardinal
numbers”. This is a definition of this latter form of expression in terms of
the first. It shows that we aren’t using the word “prove” in the second case in
the same way as in the first. In any case it is misleading to say that we have
proved the equation
D or A. Perhaps it is better
to say that we have proved its generality, though that too is misleading in
other respects.’
what we have
done here is propose it’s generality
‘Now has the
proof B answered a question, or proved an assertion true? And which is the
proof of B? Is it the group of three equations of the form µ, b, g or the class
of proofs of these equations. These equations do assert something (they don’t prove anything in the sense in which they are proved). But the proofs of µ, b g answer the
question whether these three equations are correct and prove true the assertion
that they are correct. All I can do is explain: the question whether A holds
for all cardinal numbers is to mean: “for the functions
j(x)
= a + (b + x),
y(x)
= (a + b) +x
are the equations µ, b, g valid?” And then that
question is answered by the recursive proof of A, if what that means is the
proofs of µ, b, g (or laying down of µ and the use
of it to prove b and g).
So I can say
the recursive proof shows that the equation A satisfies a certain condition;
but it isn’t the kind of condition that the equation (a + b) 2 +
= a2 +2b + b 2
has to
fulfill in order to be called “correct”. If I call A “correct” because
equations of the form µ, b, g can be proved for it, I am no longer using
the word “correct” in the
same way as
in the case of the equations µ, b, g or (a + b) 2 = a2
+2ab + b 2
What does
“1/3 = 0.3” mean? Does it mean the same as “1/3 = 0.3? Or is that division the
proof of the first equation? 1
That is, does
it have the same relationship to it as a calculation has to what is
proved?
“1/3 = 0.3” is not the same thing as
“1/2 = 0.5”;
what “1/2 =
0.5”; corresponds to is “1/3 = 0.3” not
0
“1/3 = 0.3”
1
Instead of the
notation “1/4 = 0.25” I will adopt for this occasion the following
1/4 = 0.25”. So, for example, 3/8 = 0.375.
0 0
(NB: The dash
underneath emphasizes that the remainder is equal to the dividend. So the expression
becomes the symbol for periodic division.)
.
Then I can
say, what corresponds to this proposition is not 1/3 = 0.3, but e.g.
“1/3 = 0.333”
.0.3 is not a result of division (quotient) in the same
sense as 0.375.
1
For we are
acquainted with the numeral “0.375” before the division 3/8; but what does
“0.3” mean when detached from the periodic division? – The assertion that the
.
division a :
b gives o. c as quotient is the same as the assertion that the first place of
the quotient c and the first remainder is the same as the dividend.
The relation
B to the assertion that A holds for all cardinal numbers is the same as that of
1/3 = 0.3 to 1/3 = 0.3 to 1/3 = 0.3
1
The
contradictory of the assertion “A holds for all cardinal numbers”; is one of
the equations µ, b, g is false. And the corresponding question
isn’t asking for a decision between a (x). fx and a ($x),
~fx.
The
construction of the induction is not a proof,
but a certain arrangement of proofs (a pattern in the sense of an ornament).
And one can’t exactly say either: if I prove three equations, then I prove one.
Just as the movements of a suite don’t amount to a single movement
We can also
say: we have a rule for constructing, in a certain game, decimal functions
consisting only of 3’s; but if you regard this
rule as a kind of number, it can’t be the result of a division; the only
result would be what we may call periodic division which has the form a/d = c.’
Wittgenstein
is right there are no proofs here –
but you could
well say that the advantage of the recursive theory here – in this discussion of proof – is just that it illustrates
to us that the standard notion of proof is actually irrelevant
and this is
not to say we have identified some kind of an anomaly in mathematical theory –
it is rather
to make the point that mathematical propositions and mathematical propositional
constructions – are proposals
and that
there is no ‘proof’ in propositional reality –
any proposal
– mathematical or otherwise – is open to question – open to doubt – is
uncertain
‘proof’ – is
a rhetorical device – a pretence – and one that is entirely unnecessary to a
clear understanding of the proposition – and one that is entirely unnecessary
to the full function of mathematics –
logically
speaking ‘proof’ is a myth – basically harmless – but a confusion nevertheless
– and like any confusion – one we can do without it –
it strikes me
as bad habit or at least a quaint habit
what we have
in this ‘certain arrangement of proofs’ – is a propositional practice –
or if you
like a propositional speak that
mathematicians can be comfortable with – in playing out this recursive exercise
–
and ‘proofs’
could be seen here as enabling or legitimizing deices
the real
issue is not whether there is a proof here – or just how the process stacks up
against standard proof practice –
but rather
where the propositional exercise leads – and whether what it leads to is
regarded as useful –
and just what
that amounts to is a question of mathematical theory – mathematical context –
and here of
course there is always question – doubt – uncertainty –
it is of the
nature of human space – however it is configured – however it is drawn
and finally
always a question of just what mathematicians do –
what they
construct – what propositional reality they make and inhabit –
and what
their colleagues will assent to
everyone who
plays – is in the equation – on the left-hand side of the = sign –
and in
general – everyone comes out – on the right-hand side –
and you could
well say – the argument – from either
side –
is always –
recursive
what else do
we have but the assertion of the proposition?
if this
doesn’t get the job done – we are likely to reassert –
and most
likely in a different form
the game is
rhetoric
31 Induction.
(x).j and ($x). jx. Does the induction prove the general proposition
true and the existential proposition false?
‘3 x 2 = 5 + 1
3 x (a + 1) = 3 + (3 x a) = (5 + b) + 3 = 5 + (b +
3)
Why do we call this induction the proof that (n):n >
2. É. 3 x n ≠ 5?! Well don’t you see
that if the proposition holds for n = 2, it holds for n = 3, and then for n =
4, and that it goes on like that for ever? (What am I explaining when I explain
the way a proof by induction works?) So you call it a proof of “f(2).f(3).f(4),
etc.” But isn’t it rather the form of the proofs of “f(2)” and “f(3)” and
“f(4)”, etc.? Or does that come to the
same thing? Well if I call the induction the proof of one proposition, I can do so only if that is supposed to mean no
more than it proves every proposition of a certain form. (And my expression
relies on the analogy with the relationship between the proposition “all acids
turn litmus paper red” and the proposition “sulphuric acid turns litmus paper
red”).’
yes – the form
of the proofs –
and yes –
it comes to the same thing –
and ‘form’
here is no more than a rule of presentation –
which comes
down to – syntax
there is in
truth – no ‘induction’ here at all
to
represent this action as ‘inductive’ –
is – as
Wittgenstein suggests –
to propose
an analogy –
that gets
mathematical action dead wrong
in any case –
‘sulphuric acid turns litmus paper red’ –
is a deduction from –
‘all acids
turn litmus paper red’
‘Suppose
someone says “let us check whether f(n) holds for all n” and begins to write
the series
3 x 2 = 5 + 1
3 x (2 + 1) = (3 x 2) + 3 =
(5 +1) +3 = 5 + (1 =3)
3 x (2 + 2) = (3 x (2 + 1)) + 3 = (5 +
(1 + 3)) + 3 = 5 + ((1 + 3) + 3)
and then
breaks off and says “I see it holds for all n” – So he has seen an induction! But was he looking for an induction? He didn’t have
any method for looking for one. And if he hadn’t discovered one, would he ipso facto have found a number which
does not satisfy the condition? – The rule for checking can’t be: let’s see
whether there is an induction or a case for the law which does not hold.– If
the law of excluded middle doesn’t hold, that can only mean that our expression
isn’t comparable to a proposition.’
‘let us check
whether f(n) holds for all n … and then breaks off and says “I see it holds for
all n’
here you can make
a rule that ‘f(n) holds for all n’ –
but you can’t
see that ‘f(n) holds for all n’ – or check that ‘f(n) holds for
all n’
‘So he has
seen an induction!’ –
an induction
– does not end in a generality –
so ‘seeing an
induction’ – is better described – is more accurately described as – not
seeing that f(n) holds for all n’ –
but assuming
nevertheless that it will –
the ‘seeing’
– the ‘checking’ here – only makes sense if the generality is already in
place –
‘that f(n)
holds for all n’ – can only be a rule – a rule in a game –
and if this
is understood – the question of proof – does not arise –
and even if
it did – if you were to still hold to this notion of ‘proof’ – induction does
not fit the bill –
perhaps he
stopped ‘checking’ – because he got sick of being involved in a pointless
exercise
‘When we say
that an induction proves the general proposition, we think: it proves that this
proposition and not its contradictory is true. But what would be the
contradictory of the proposition proved? Well, that ($n).
~ fn is the
case. Here we combine two concepts: one derived from my current concept of the
proof of (n). fn, and another taken from the analogy with ($x).
jx
. Of course we have to remember that “(n).fn” isn’t a proposition until I have
a criterion for its truth; and then it only has the sense that the criterion
gives it. Although, before getting the criterion, I could look out for something
like an analogy to (x). (fx). What is the opposite of what the induction
proves? The proof of (a + b) 2 = a2 + 2ab + b2 works out this equation in
contrast to something like (a + b)2,
= a2 + 3ab + b2. What does the inductive
proof work out? The equations: 3 x 2 = 5 +1, 3 x (a + 1) = (3 x a) + 3, (5 + b)
+ 3 = 5 + (b + 3) as opposed to things like 3 x 2 = 5 + 6, 3 x (a + 1) = (4 x
a) + 2, etc. But this opposite does not correspond to the proposition ($x).
jx
– Further, what does conflict with the induction is every proposition of the
form ~f (n), i.e.
the propositions “~f(2)”,
“~f(3)”,
etc.; that is to say the induction is the common element in the working out of
f(2), f(3), etc.; but it isn’t the working out of “all propositions of the form
f(n)”, since of course no class of propositions occurs in the proof that I call
“all propositions of the form f(n)”. Each one of the calculations is a checking
of the proposition of the form f(n)”. I was able to investigate the correctness
of this proposition and employ a method to check it; all the induction did was
bring this into a simple form. But if I call the induction “the proof of a
general proposition”, I can’t ask whether that proposition is correct (any more
than whether the form of the cardinal number is correct). Because the things I
call inductive proofs give me no method of checking
whether the general proposition is correct or incorrect; instead, the method
has to show me how to work out (check) whether or not an induction can be
constructed for a particular case within a system of propositions. (If I may so
put it, what it checked in this way is whether all n have this or that
property; not whether all of them have it, or whether there are some that don’t have it. For example, we work out
that the equation x2 + 3x + 1 = 0 has no rational roots
(that there is no rational number that …), and the equation x2
+ 2x + 1/2 = 0 has none, but the equation x2 +
2x + 1 = 0 does etc.’
‘When we say
that an induction proves the general proposition, we think: it proves that this
proposition and not its contradictory is true.
an induction proves nothing
at best you
can say – an induction proposes a
generality
‘But what
would be the contradictory of the proposition proved?
the
contradictory?
if an induction proposes a generality – its contradictory –
would be to deny the generality –
effectively – an argument against induction – or the idea
that a generality can result from particular ‘observations’
‘Of course we have to remember that “(n).fn” isn’t
a proposition until I have a criterion for its truth; and then it only has the
sense that the criterion gives it.’
anything put
– is open to question – open to doubt – is a proposition
the question of the ‘criterion of truth’ – is the
question of the acceptance of the
proposal – of the proposition
particular language forms – i.e. mathematics – have
rules – rules of procedures – for determining truth / acceptance
if you play the game – you play within the rules of
that game
‘What is the opposite of what the induction
proves?’
an inductive ‘argument’ proposes a generality –
the ‘opposite of a generality’ will be the particular – going – nowhere –
so is
there a proposal?
you could say the particular is proposed – and
that’s it –
but quite clearly – if this is the best you can say
about what is proposed –
then ‘the opposite of the induction’ –
is no
proposal
‘Hence we
find it odd if we are told that the induction is a proof of a general
proposition; for we feel rightly that in the language of induction we couldn’t
have posed the general question at all. It wasn’t as if we began with an
alternative between which we had to decide. (We only seemed to, so long as we
had in mind a calculus with finite classes).
Prior to the
proof asking about the general proposition made no sense at all, and so wasn’t
even a question, because the question would only have made sense if a general
method of decision had been known before
the particular proof was discovered.
The proof by
induction isn’t something that settles a disputed question.’
‘for we feel
rightly that in the language of induction we couldn’t have posed the general
question at all’
from an observation or an instance – one might propose a generality –
but it is no more than speculation –
speculation is not proof
and this is why it seems odd that anyone would
propose that the induction is a proof of
a general proposition
a proposition is a proposal – open to question –
open to doubt – uncertain –
this logic applies to any and all propositions
so the form of the proposition is not logically
relevant – i.e. – particular or general
any proposal – any proposition – is open to
question –
the inductive argument to my mind is no more than
suggestive –
but strictly speaking that can be said of any
argument – or any form of argument – to a proposal – to a proposition
does induction have a place in mathematics?
does suggestion – propositional suggestion – have a
place in mathematics?
yes – and logically speaking – does it matter where
the suggestion comes from – how it is explained?
no
in mathematics – and in forms of mathematics –
procedures and practices have been developed –
their only justification – in the end – is use – is
the practice
‘The proof by
induction isn’t something that settles a disputed question’
logically speaking there is no settling of a disputed
question
questions do get ‘settled’ – but here we are talking about
pragmatics
as for induction – it is a form of speculation
if understood correctly – what it does is raise questions –
not settle them
‘If you say: “the proposition ‘(n)fn’ follows from the
induction” only means that every proposition of the form f(n) follows from the
induction and “the proposition ($n).
~ fn
contradicts the induction” only means “every proposition of the form ~ f(n) is
disproved by the induction”, then we may agree; but we shall ask: what is the
correct way to use the expression “the proposition (n).f(n)”? What is its
grammar? (For from the fact that I use it in certain contexts it doesn’t follow
that I use it everywhere in the same way as the expression “the proposition
(x). jx”).’
the proposition is put
and yes you can argue that it is the result of an induction
– but this is neither here nor there
all you do in such an argument is put forward a proposal as
to how the proposition came about –
might be of interest to do this – might not be –
it’s basically a background story
the issue is the proposal – the proposition itself –
which is to say – does it have legs – will it run?
now to then say – ‘(n)fn follows from the induction’ – is –
when all is said and done – to propose
(n)fn –
linking it to another proposition – the proposition that you
say resulted from the ‘induction’ – is an argument –
and if you are to say it follows from it – I would imagine
that means the argument is deductive
–
and yes – in a systematic propositional activity – we like
to propose links –
but again the issue is the proposition that is proposed –
an account of ‘how it came about’ – is not important – it’s
an accessory – and this applies to deductive argument as much as it does to
inductive argument
‘what is the
correct way to use the expression “the proposition (n).f(n)”? What is its
grammar? (For from the fact that I use it in certain contexts it doesn’t follow
that I use it everywhere in the same way as the expression “the proposition
(x). jx”)’
–
any proposition – any proposal – is open to
question – to doubt – is uncertain
and it is just this that enables the use of
propositions – in different contexts –
how one uses one’s propositions – yes – is a matter
of context –
grammar – or the logic of use – is a matter of
context –
we are best to see ‘grammar’ as propositional
flexibility
‘Suppose that people argue whether the quotient of
the division 1/3 must contain only threes, but had no method of deciding it.
Suppose one of them noticed the inductive property of 1.0 /3 = 0.3 and said:
now I know that there must be only threes in the
quotient. The others had not thought of that kind of decision. I suppose that
they had vaguely imagined some kind of decision by checking each step, though
of course they could never have reached a decision in this way. If they hold
onto their extensional viewpoint, the induction does not produce a decision
because in the case of each extension of the quotient it shows that it consists
of nothing but threes. But if they drop their extensional viewpoint the
induction decides nothing, or nothing that is not decided by working out 1.0 /3
= 0.3, namely that the remainder is the same as the
dividend. But nothing else. Certainly there is a
valid question that may arise, namely, is the remainder left after this
division the same as the dividend? The question now takes the place of the old
extensional question, and of course I can keep the old wording, but it is now
extremely misleading since it always makes it look as if having
the induction were only a vehicle – a vehicle that
can take us into infinity. (This is also connected with the fact that the sign
“etc.” refers to an internal property of the bit of the series that precedes
it, and not to its extension.)’
‘Suppose that people argue whether the quotient of
the division 1/3 must contain only threes, but had no method of deciding it.’ –
if so these people are speculating –
I see ‘method’ as basically a back story – a
‘justification’ if you like – in any case –
an argument for
a propositional use –
now advancing such an argument – may well put any
critics at bay – and indeed – if the argument / method advanced is regarded by
other practitioners as status quo – or at least acceptable – then the proposal
will be endorsed by the practitioners
however this has to with practice – and the
rhetoric of practice
whether the methodological argument – whatever it
might be – is accepted – is logically speaking
– irrelevant
any argument – any method – from a logical point of
view – is open to question – open to doubt – and regardless of how it is
received and acted upon – uncertain –
a proposal – a proposition – is – that put –
and as such – from a logical point view – only ever
in the realm of speculation
propositional practice or use is only ever
speculation proceeded with
it is the proposition put – that is of significance
– that is where we start
methodological argument – is about persuasion for
acceptance
‘Certainly there is a valid question that may
arise, namely, is the remainder left after this division the same as the
dividend?’
yes – a valid question – but no more valid than any
question of interpretation
really the issue is not ‘numbers’ as such – but the
game – the numbers game –
numbers as such are game steps – or markers of game
action
the real question is – how is the game being used –
in what propositional / mathematical context is the
game being played?
there are always options –
when a practice is determined – decided upon – the
play begins
‘Of course the question “is there a rational number
that is the root of x2 x 3x +1 = 0?”
is decided by an induction; but in this case I have
actually constructed a method of forming inductions; and the question is only
so phrased because it is a matter of constructing inductions. That is, a
question is settled by induction, if I can look for the induction in advance;
if everything in its sign is settled in advance bar my acceptance or rejection
of it in such a way that I can decide yes or no by calculating; as I can
decide, for instance, in whether 5/7 the remainder is equal to the divided or
not. (The employment in these cases of the expressions “all…” and “there is …”
has a certain similarity with the employment of the word “infinite” in the
sentence “today I bought a straightedge with an infinite radius of curvature”)’
yes – the methodology – is the proposal put forward – to settle the question
an inductive method – an inductive proposal – may
well be the standard approach to this question – in practice
however this is not to say that a rule governed
deductive approach could not be proposed –
it could well be argued that such an approach is in
fact the ground of any induction –
and that any induction here is just a
methodological short cut – in the shadow of the deductive argument
the more general point here is that whatever is
proposed – inductive – deductive – or other – is valid if its argument is accepted by the mathematical community – whatever that amounts to
and this is an issue – not of logic – but of
persuasion
if you propose an answer to a question – the answer
– if it is to be convincing to yourself and to others will involve argument
argument only ever ‘settles the matter’ – if the
argument – for whatever reason – stops
and there is agreement
however logically speaking the argument can always
go on
any proposal – is open to question
‘The periodicity of 1/3 = 0.3 decides
nothing that has been left open. Suppose
1
someone had been looking in vain, before the
discovery of the periodicity, for a 4 in the development of 1/3, he still
couldn’t have significantly put the question “is there a 4 in the development
of 1/3?” That is, independently of the fact that he didn’t actually discover
any 4s, we can convince him that he doesn’t have a method for deciding his
question. Or we might say: quite apart from the result of his activity we could
instruct him about the grammar of his question and the nature of his search (as
we might instruct a contemporary mathematician about analogous problems). “But
as a result of discovering the periodicity he does stop looking for a 4! No.
The discovery of the periodicity will cure him if he makes the appropriate adjustment. We might ask him: “Well
how about it, do you still want to look for a 4?” (Or has the periodicity so to
say changed your mind?)
The discovery of the periodicity is really the
construction of a new symbol and a new calculus. For it is misleading to say
that it consists in our having realised
that the first remainder is the same as the dividend. For if we had asked
someone unacquainted with periodic division whether the first remainder in this
division was the same as the dividend, of course he would have answered “yes”;
and so he did realise. But that doesn’t mean he must have realised the
periodicity: that is, it wouldn’t mean he had discovered the calculus with the
sign a/b =c’
a
‘The periodicity of 1/3 = 0.3 decides
nothing that has been left open’ –
1
this is quite correct
‘Or we might say: quite apart from the result of
his activity we could instruct him about the grammar of his question and the
nature of his search (as we might instruct a contemporary mathematician about
analogous problems’ –
what this amounts to is that he is not playing the
game as it is played – and that he is looking for a 4 in the development
of 1/3 – suggests he is far from
understanding the game as played
‘The discovery of the periodicity will cure him if he makes the appropriate adjustment.’
and the appropriate adjustment is understanding
this mathematical game – as it is constructed and played
discovering the periodicity – might well point him
in the right direction
and yes –
‘The discovery of the periodicity is really the
construction of a new symbol and a new calculus’
a new game – a game that can be played within a
game –
and – indeed the periodicity game is played because
it is useful
a/b = c is a formal statement of the game –
a
a formal representation of periodicity
‘Isn’t what I am saying what Kant meant, by saying
that 5 + 7 = 12 is not analytic but synthetic a priori?’
what we have is rule governed propositional actions
if you follow the rules of the propositional
constructions – you play the game
the ‘game’ simply is playing according to the rules
–
if you don’t know the rules – or if you don’t
follow them – you don’t play –
if you question the rules – you don’t play the game
a rule – is a proposal – a game – a set of
proposals –
any proposal – is open to question – open to doubt
– uncertain –
however – if you want to play – and this is the
essence of mathematics – you regard the proposals in mathematical games – as rules
how these games come about – how they are
discovered – is not mathematics
any account of such matters is propositional
speculation –
what we can say is that the games that are played
in mathematics – are played because they are regarded – by the players – for
whatever reason – as significant – as
useful –
if by ‘analytic’ here – is meant that 5 + 7 = 12 –
is a rule governed propositional – then ‘analytic’ tells a part of the story
if ‘a priori’
– is understood to mean ‘rule governed’ – and
‘synthetic’ – that any
proposition is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain –
then you have with
‘synthetic a priori’ – a
comprehensive description / picture of the logic and practise of mathematics
32. Is there
a further step from the recursive proof
to the generalization? Doesn’t the recursion schema already say all that is to
be said?
‘Is there a further step from the recursive proof
to the generalization?’
the recursive proof to the generalization – is of
course an induction –
and I think it can be said that every induction has a missing step –
either that –
or you have to accept an infinity of steps where
the only cut off point is fatigue
seriously though – the relation of the recursive
schema to the generalization – is best described as suggestive
that mathematicians take the recursive proof as a
proof of a generalization – is I would suggest best seen as no more than
mathematical speculation –
and again such speculation can be useful – can function
as a platform or a step in propositional exploration
mathematics is presented as strict rule governed
activity – and this works in so far as those involved buy that story –
however the practices and the rules governing
mathematical practice – are open to question – open to doubt are logically
speaking – uncertain –
the real charm of mathematics is its pretence
‘Doesn’t the recursion schema already say all that
is to be said?’
well – the question is – just what does it say?
Wittgenstein goes on to say –
‘But really the recursion shows nothing but itself,
just as periodicity too shows nothing but itself’ –
a sanguine view – but on the money nevertheless
for mine though the issue comes down to the
question – how is recursion used?
and that I would say is really an empirical
question – a question of mathematical practice –
that is what mathematicians in fact do with the
recursion argument
-.-
the recursive proof is a propositional game –
‘the point is whether it has the same clearly
defined meaning in all cases’ –
‘clearly defined meaning’ in any case – is open to
question –
‘And isn’t it the case that the recursive proofs in
fact show the same for all proved equations?’
yes – that is the idea of the game
‘And doesn’t that mean that between the recursive
proof and the proposition it proves there is always the same (internal)
relation?’
yes – that is the game
‘Anyway it is quite clear that there must be a
recursive, or better “proof” of this kind (A proof conveying the insight that
“that’s the way it must be with all numbers”)’
I.e. it seems clear to me; and it seems that by a
process of iteration I could make the correctness of these theorems for the
cardinal numbers intelligible to someone else.’
‘that’s the way it must be with all numbers’ – just
is the game that is played
mathematicians look for proof – simply because they
are at sixes and sevens regarding mathematics as a game –
the idea of the proof is to ground mathematics in
certainty –
to give it a status beyond that of the game
now you can put this down to psychological
insecurity or simply epistemological ignorance –
nevertheless – it is standard practise
‘proof’ is a propositional game played with
propositional games – that is the
game
‘I.e. it seems to me that by a process of iteration
I could make the correctness of these theorems for cardinal numbers
intelligible to someone else’
iteration – the idea here is that if you assert
long and hard enough – the poor bastard at the end of your iteration – will
just nod –
the cat is out of the bag here – all this is about
is rhetoric – not logic – persuasion – not critical thought –
and in any case not everyone is going to fall for
it –
so Wittgenstein’s ‘it seems to me ..’ – is wishful
thinking –
that is of course if he actually believes what he
has proposed here –
still so far I haven’t seen from Wittgenstein any
recognition of the central place of rhetoric is mathematics –
so I take him at his word
‘But how do I know that 28 + (45 + 17) = (28 + 45)
+ 17 without having proved it? How can a general proof give me a particular
proof? I might after all go through the particular proof, and how would the two
proofs meet in it? What happens if they do not agree?’
‘But how do I know that 28 + (45 + 17) = (28 + 45)
+ 17 without having proved it?’
what this comes down to is rules – rules of practice – specifically the rules governing
addition –
any so called proof – will at best – be nothing
more than – a restatement of those rules
and any ‘proof’ – presented as some form of
addition to the rules – will thus be
irrelevant and unnecessary
the ‘proof-game’ is not necessary on any level – if
it is realized that the practise – the mathematical practise – is rule governed
‘How can a general proof give me a particular
proof? I might after all go through the particular proof, and how would the two
proofs meet in it? What happens if they do not agree?’
I would think that a general proof and a particular
proof are different arguments –
and if the general proof applies to the particular
proof – that will require argument
if they don’t agree – the reason as for why – will
be the subject of further argument
mathematics is a rule governed propositional action
–
if you know the rules – accept the rules – you can
play the game –
if you don’t know the rules or don’t accept them –
you are not in the game
‘In other word: suppose I wanted to show someone
that the associative law is really a part of the nature of number, and isn’t
something that only accidentally holds in this particular case; wouldn’t I use
a process of iteration to try to show that the law holds and must go on
holding? Well – that shows us what we mean here by saying that a law must hold
for all numbers.
And what is to prevent us calling this process a
proof of the law?’
‘that a law must
hold …’ –
this is no more than assertion
and that is iteration – assertion – and reassertion
‘And what is to prevent us calling this process a
proof of the law?’
well yes –
all we have here is rhetoric – persuasion
does iteration – persuade?
I guess so – if it is held to persuade – by those
who practise it – and those who are subject to it
and I suppose assertion and reassertion – is one
sense honest and transparent –
and yes – logically speaking – this is all proof is
– all it comes down to –
reassertion –
in whatever form that takes
so in the beginning and in the end all we have is assertion
‘proof’ – is not a logical concept –
proof is a form of rhetoric
‘The concept of “making something comprehensible”
is a boon in a case like this.
For we might say: the criterion of whether
something is a proof of a proposition is whether it could be used for making it
comprehensible. (Of course here again all that is involved is an extension of
our grammatical investigation of the word “proof” and not any psychological
interest in the process of making things comprehensible.)’
a proof will be – despite any pretensions of
grandeur – no more than a restatement of
the proposition
perhaps a restatement – as in a different
formulation – will facilitate comprehension?
and in any case comprehension – with or without the
‘proof’ – will in practice –
come down to understanding the rules governing the
use of the proposition in whatever context it is put to use
beyond this – comprehension is not something we can
put limits on –
there are always questions of breadth and depth
‘ “The proposition is proved for all numbers by the
recursive procedure.” That is the expression that is so misleading. It sounds
as if here a proposition saying that such and such holds for all cardinal
numbers is proved by a particular route, and as if this route was a route
through a space of conceivable routes.
But really the recursion shows nothing but itself,
just as periodicity too shows nothing but itself.’
yes –
what can we say of the proposal – ‘The proposition
is proved for all numbers by the recursive procedure’?
it’s only value seems to me to be that of protecting the proposition from question –
protecting it from doubt
and of course – logically speaking there is no
protection –
so?
we have to view it as a rhetorical device –
and look – an unnecessary one at that –
the proposition – if it has value – will be put to
work –
claiming something like ‘eternal proof’ – is irrelevant
–
it will function – in whatever context it is used –
or it won’t
‘We are not saying that when f(1) holds and when f(c + 1) follows from f (c),
the proposition f(x) is therefore true of all cardinal numbers; but: “the
proposition f(x) holds for all cardinal numbers” means “it holds for x= 1, and f(c + 1) follows from f(c)”.
Here the connection with generality in finite
domains is quite clear, for in a finite domain that would certainly be a proof
that f(x) holds for all values of x, and that is the reason why we say in the
arithmetical case that f(x) holds for all numbers.’
the connection with generality in finite domains is
functional – is operational
the claim of generality to an infinite domain – is
functionally and operationally irrelevant
the claim of generality to an infinite domain might
suggest greater power – suggest a greater – indeed endless scope –
but any such suggestion has no effective baring on
any particular mathematical action performed
such a suggestion only has rhetorical value
‘At least I have to say that any objection that
holds against the proof of B holds also e.g. against the formula (a
+ b)n = etc.
Here too, I would have to say, I am merely assuming
an algebraic rule that agrees with the inductions of arithmetic.’
mathematics is a rule governed propositional action
–
so called inductions – if they have a role in
mathematics – are pointers to the rules of mathematics – or applications of the
rules
here we have the issue of the proper way to
understand mathematical action
induction in mathematics – is the poor man’s
explanation –
yes certain actions can be represented as
inductions – but any such representation
lacks overall perspective – and is therefore inadequate
and as for proof –
if you dispense with the rhetoric of proof – what
you end up with is decision – the
decision to proceed –
and yes – any decision – is open to question – open
to doubt – and is – despite its action – uncertain
‘f(n) x (a + b) = f(n + 1)
f(1) = a + b)
therefore f(1) x (a + b) = (a + b)2 =
f(2)
therefore f(2) x (a + b) = (a + b)3 =
f(3), etc.
So far all is clear. But then: “therefore (a + b)n = f(n)”
Is a further inference drawn here? Is there still
something to be established?’
here we can ask is (a + b)n = f(n) a conclusion
of an induction – or the first premise of a deduction?
the inductive argument always leaves us with the
problem of the final step to the generalization – and the problem is that there
is no final step –
so you get nowhere with induction –
(a + b)n = f(n) – as a rule (and all
rules are rules of thumb) – clears the way –
and enables us to get on with it –
get on with the game
‘But if someone shows me the formula shows me the
formula (a + b)2 = f(n) I could ask: how have we got there? And the answer
would be the group
f(n) x (a +b) = f(n +1)
f(1) = a + b
So isn’t it a proof of the algebraic proposition? –
Or is it rather an answer to the question “what does the algebraic proposition
mean?”’
‘how have we got there?’ –
is to ask for the path taken to the proposition
now the fact of it is that logically speaking –
f(n) x (a +b) = f(n +1)
f(1) = a + b
does not get us to – (a + b)2 = f(n)
however –
f(n) x (a +b) = f(n +1)
f(1) = a + b
may just be the fact
of how (a + b)2 = f(n) is arrived at –
the point being that yes there is the problem of
the inductive argument – but nevertheless that is the route taken to (a + b)2
= f(n)
it’s the argument of practise
and you can ask – really does it matter where (a +
b)2 = f(n) came from – how you got there?
the idea being that the issue is rather – does it
make sense – is it consistent with operating rules – can we work with it?
yes there is a place for explanation – but what we
are talking about here is argument –
and usually argument after the fact
as for proof – what proof amounts to is decision to proceed –
and any decision is open to question – open to
doubt – uncertain
‘I want to say: once you’ve got the induction, it’s
all over.’
once you’ve got the induction – you’ve got nothing
–
what you have to have is the rule – and once you
have the rule – you will see the poverty of induction
‘The proposition that A holds for all cardinal
numbers is really the complex B plus its proof, the proof of b
and g.
But that shows that this proposition is not a proposition in the same sense as
an equation, and this proof is not in the same sense as a proof of a
proposition.
Don’t forget that it isn’t that we first of all
have the concept of proposition, and then come to know that equations are mathematical
propositions, and later that there are also other kinds of mathematical
propositions.’
a proposition is a proposal – open to question –
open to doubt – uncertain
‘The proposition that A holds for all cardinal
numbers is really the complex B plus its proof, the proof of b
and g.’
– is a proposal – open to question – open to doubt – uncertain
an equation is a proposal – open to question – open
to doubt – uncertain
the point is that there is no logical distinction
between any proposition – any proposal
propositions are distinguished – differentiated –
in terms of use – in terms of practice and practice traditions
mathematical propositions function as
game-propositions – that is as rule governed propositions
if you wish to play the game – you look for the
rules of practise – and if you are to play the game – you follow the rules
the propositions – the rules – the games – are all
open to question – to doubt – are
uncertain
investigating propositional uncertainty is not
playing the game – is not doing mathematics
investigating uncertainty is doing logic proper
doing mathematics is following the rules without
question – doubt – or uncertainty
that is how you play the game
33 How far
does a recursive proof deserve the name “proof”? How far is a step in
accordance with the paradigm A justified by the proof of B?
‘We cannot appoint a calculation to be a proof of a
proposition’
I think Wittgenstein has hit the nail of the head
here –
but it strikes me that it was perhaps a lucky shot
–
but nevertheless well put
if appointing a proof – is quite simply ad hoc – what is the alternative?
that the proof is in the proposition – and can be teased out?
if it’s in the proposition – then it is the
proposition
the proposition is a proposal – open to question –
open to doubt –
if you ‘proof’ a proposition – as in make it
certain – you destroy it –
what you have then is not a proposition – rather a
prejudice
so the point is just that there is no relation between a proposition and a
so called proof
or the relation between the two is contradictory
the best we can do regarding establishing a
proposition is to argue for its place and function in a working context
‘I would like to say: Do we have to call the recursive calculation the proof of proposition I?
That is won’t another relationship do?’

yes – the ‘recursive calculation’ might better be
described as a game – a propositional game – the recursive game
‘(What is infinitely difficult is to “see all
around” the calculus.)’
whether you can see ‘all around’ the calculus or
not – what are dealing with is the calculus –
and the point is to use it
‘In the one case “The step justified” means it can
be carried out in accordance with definite forms that have been given. In the
other case the justification might be that the step is taken in accordance with
paradigms that themselves satisfy a certain condition.’
yes
and in any case ‘justification’ – will be just what
it is decided that it is –
‘justification’ of any kind – is rhetoric
‘Suppose that for a certain board game rules are
given containing words with no “r” in them, and that I call a rule justified,
if it contains no “r”. Suppose someone then said, he had laid down one rule for a certain game, namely,
that its moves must obey rules containing no “r”s. Is that a rule of the game
(in the first sense)? Isn’t the game played in accordance with the class of
rules all of which have only to satisfy the first rule?’
the one rule – or a class of rules – one game or
two games?
the difference is in what is given –
in the first case rules (plural) are given – those
rules are the rules of play – and no others
in the second case the one rule is given –
the second case effectively argues for an extension
of the game – in that more rules than
those given in the first case are allowed – and the argument is that they are
consistent with those rules given in the first case
if the extension is allowed the first game is seen
to be contained in the second – and you now have one game –
if not you have two different – but similar – games
it’s really just a question of how the game or
games are constructed –
do you have a set of rules – a finite set – that is
not to be messed with?
or do you have one rule that allows for – an
unknown number of other rules that it is proposed are consistent with that one
rule?
it depends just on what kind of game you want to
play –
that’s all
‘Someone shows me the construction of B and then
says that A has been proved. I ask “How? All I see is that you have used µ[r] to build a construction
around A” Then he says “But when that is possible, I say A is proved”. To that
I answer: “That only shows me the new sense you attach to ‘prove’.”
‘Someone shows me the construction of B and then
says that A has been proved’ –
and then says
–
this is really all it ever comes to – what is said – and if you like – the force in
which it is delivered and received –
which is to say – one way or another – the matter
is purely rhetorical –
a straight out assertion – or an involved argument
– what we are dealing with is persuasion
‘In one sense it means that you have used µ[r] to construct a paradigm
in such and such a way, in another, it means as before that an equation is in
accordance with the paradigm.’
ok – but what
has any of this got to do with proof?
‘If we ask
“is that a proof or not?” we are keeping to the word-language.’
‘is that a
proof or not?’ – is to ask –
do I accept
this proposition or not?
one’s reasons
for acceptance or rejection can be – will be – many and varied – and will
depend on one’s state of knowledge
that
‘authorities’ – whoever they are at the time –
may decide
one way or the other – will probably determine what happens next –
the point is
– a decision is required –
and yes –
given that the matter is not frivolous – reasons are to be expected – and
inspected –
and if we
stick with what Wittgenstein here calls ‘keeping to the word language’ –
we follow and
endorse a language-ritual
‘Of course
there can be no objection if someone says: if the terms of a step in a
construction are of such and such a kind, I say that the legitimacy of the step
is proved.’
‘of such and
such a kind’ – is open to question –
what you have
when ‘the terms of a step in a construction are of such and such a kind’ – is a
proposal – open to question – open to doubt – uncertain
at best ‘the
legitimacy of the step’ is argued –
to say that
it is proved – is to say – there is no argument –
and if that
is the case then what we have is a proof of ignorance and stupidity –
and in a
place where you would least expect it –
be that as it
may – we have language rituals –which function –
and largely
because – they continue to function
‘What is it
in me that resist the idea of B as a proof of A? In the first place I observe
that in my calculation I now here use the proposition about “all cardinal
numbers”. I used r to construct the complex B
and then I took the step to the equation A; in all that there was no mention of
“all cardinal numbers”. (This proposition is a bit of word-language
accompanying the calculation, and can only mislead me.) But it isn’t only that
this general proposition drops out, it is that no other takes its place.’
‘What is it
in me that resist the idea of B as a proof of A?’ –
perhaps at base something of an ontological
uneasiness – B is not A – so how would B prove A?
and following on from this the idea would be that
the proof of A is in A – or just simply is A
and if so – we may as well drop the idea of proof –
as something outside of whatever is to be proved
and if you do that the notion of proof evaporates
what this amounts to is A is A – meaning A is well
formed and functional –
or it is not –
and if it is not well-formed and functional – it is
not only not A – it is not anything of significance
‘But it isn’t
only that this general proposition drops out, it is that no other takes its
place’ –
yes – the
argument is changed – a different
argument is put – A and B are different arguments
B is as it
were the platform that is used to launch to A
you might say
there is a trajectory – a propositional trajectory –
and the
action of one to the other?
perhaps best
explained as a quantum jump
and that I
suggest is in fact a good model for all propositional action
I understand
that people want to pin down (propositional) reality –
and the
reason for that is insecurity – metaphysical insecurity –
and there is
nothing wrong with that –
the issue is
how do you understand it?
do you regard
it as something that should be can be eliminated – with proofs – with
explanations – etc. –
or do you –
as I would suggest – see it as a the reality we must embrace as the source of
our freedom and creativity?
as the source
of true joy – yes really –
embrace it or
not – it is the reality we face
‘So the
proposition asserting the generalization drops out; “nothing is proved”, “nothing follows”.
“But the
equation A follows, it is that which takes the place of the general
proposition.” Well, to what extent does it follow? Obviously, I am using “follows”
in a sense
quite different from the normal one, because what A follows from isn’t a
proposition. And that is why we feel that the word “follows” isn’t being
correctly applied.’
A is proposed
whether A takes the place of the general proposition or not
‘Well, to what extent does it follow?’
best to understand ‘follows’ here – in a straight out
literal sense –
what follows – is what comes after
if A follows from an argument regarding the generalization –
then A is proposed in response to that argument
whatever lead to A is what A follows from
if A came about some other way – so be it –
whatever led to A is what it follows from
here of course we are just dealing with circumstance –
and however it is described –
that is to say – however it is proposed
‘If you say
“it follows from the complex B that a = (b + c) = (a + b) + c” we feel giddy.
We feel that somehow or other you’ve said something nonsensical although
outwardly it sounds correct.’
when it is
said that a = (b + c) = (a + b) + c follows from the complex B – it is only
‘nonsensical’ – if the steps to the equation – do not follow a standard
practice
‘That an
equation follows, already has a meaning (has its own definite grammar).’
yes – and by
‘grammar’ here we mean an account – or a theory of practice or procedure
‘If I am told
“A follows from B”, I want to ask: “what follows?” That a + (b + c) is equal to
(a + b) + c, is something postulated, it doesn’t follow in the normal way from
an equation.’
‘If I am told
“A follows from B”, I want to ask: “what follows?’
what ‘follows’ mean here – is open to question – open to
doubt – is uncertain
whatever is proposed for ‘follows’ will be subject to
argument
and any argument will only be resolved – by practise –
by what those involved in the practise decide ‘follows’
means
‘That a + (b
+ c) is equal to (a + b) + c, is something postulated, it doesn’t follow in the
normal way from an equation.’
the point is that if it is proposed that a + (b + c) is equal to (a + b) + c –
follows from an equation –
then again we
need argument to that effect
and if the
argument is accepted by those involved –
then indeed
it follows
‘We can’t fit
our concept of following from to A and B; it doesn’t fit’ –
‘following
from A and B’ – is whatever step is taken
from A and B
‘following
from’ – is taking the step –
‘following
from’ – is not really the issue – the issue is whether the step taken has an
acceptable argument –
if the
argument of the step doesn’t have support –
then the step
will be regarded as a – misstep
‘ “I will
prove to you that a +(b +n) = (a + b) + n”. No one then expects to see the
complex B. You expect to hear another rule for a, b, and n permitting the
passage from one side to another. If instead of that I am given B with the
schema r
I can’t call
it a proof, because I mean something else by “proof”.
I shall very
likely say something like “oh, so that’s what you call a “proof”, I had
imagined …”’
yes –
different concepts of proof – different propositional games – which is to say
different rules – and different rules of procedure –
different
decision making processes
‘The proof of
17 + (18 +5) = (17 +18) + 5 is certainly carried out in accordance with the
schema B, and this numerical proposition is of the form A. Or again: B is a
proof of the numerical proposition; but for that very reason, it isn’t a proof
of A.’
yes – A and B
are different propositional games
‘ “I will
derive A1, AII, A111 from a single proposition
– This of course makes one think of a derivation that makes use of these propositions – We think we shall be given
smaller links of some kind to replace all these large ones in the chain.
Here we have
a definite picture; and we are offered something quite different.
The inductive
proof puts the equation together as it were crossways instead of lengthways.’
the inductive
process here does ‘put together’ – it is a method of construction –
the inductive
process of constructing an equation – is not a proof of the equation
look at it
this way –
if you are
building a building – your method of
constructing – is not a guarantee of the integrity of the materials that
you use
‘ “If we work
out the derivation, we finally come to the point at which the construction of B
is completed. But at this point we say “therefore this equation holds”! But
these words now don’t mean the same thing as they do when we elsewhere deduce
an equation from equations. The words “The equation follows from it” already
have a meaning. And although an equation is constructed here, it is by a
different principle.’
yes –
different constructions – different methods – different games
and as for
‘holds’ –
‘holds’ here
– is best understood as – proposed –
which is to
say ‘standing’ – or ‘up and running’ –
ready to go
‘If I say “The
equation follows from the complex”, then here an equation is ‘following’ from
something that is not an equation.
yes –
and the
complex functions as an argument for the
step to the equation
it is the
equation – the game that is to be played – that is significant – that is
relevant –
the argument
to it – the road to it – yes – really amounts to context –
the context out of which the equation emerges –
it’s
propositional history – if in fact that is its history
‘We can’t
say: if the equation follows from B, then it does follow from a proposition,
namely µ. b. g;
for what matters is how I get A from
that proposition; whether I do so in accordance with a rule of inference; and
what the relationship is between the equation and the proposition µ. b. g. (The rule leading to A in this
case makes a kind of cross-section through µ. b. g;
it doesn’t view the proposition in the same way as the rule of inference
does.)’
yes we can say – ‘if the equation follows from B, then it does
follow from a proposition, namely µ. b. g’
–
for B is a
proposition – is a proposal
look how you get from one proposition to another –
in any propositional context –
is up for question – a matter of doubt – is at all
times – uncertain –
where this matter is held to be of importance – as
it is in mathematics – then it is the subject of argument –
and yes we do feel more comfortable if we can say
how we got from ‘a’ to ‘b’ – and it is always of interest to see what is
proposed – and what is finally agreed upon –
whatever propositional jump we make – and however
it is explained or accounted for the point is we never leave – uncertainty
‘If we have
been promised a derivation of A from µ and now see the step from
B to A, we feel like saying “oh that isn’t what was meant.” It is as if someone
had promised to give me something and then says: see, I’m giving you my trust.’
yes – it is
not the way expected – it is not how we play the game
‘The fact
that the step from B to A is not an inference indicates also what I meant when
I said that the logical product µ. b. g
does not express the generalization.’
yes – a logical product will always fall short of
the generalization
‘I say that AI, AII etc. are used in proving (a + b)2
= etc. because the steps from (a + b)2
to a2 + 2ab + b2
are all of the form AI or
AII, etc. In this sense the step in III from
(b + 1) + a to (b + a) + 1
is also made in accordance with AI, but the step from
a + n to n + a isn’t!’
again – a + n to n + a –
just is a different game to (b + 1) + a to (b + a) + 1 – and so how can AI
be relevant?
‘The fact that we say “the
correctness of the equation is proved” shows that not every construction of an
equation is a proof.’
a construction of an
equation – any construction – is just that – a construction
a construction is really
all you have – that’s it –
different constructions –
different ways to the equation –
which means different
proposals – different arguments or steps to the equation
proof is just a rhetorical
overwrite that has nothing to do with the construction – and nothing to do with
the equation –
at best it is the decision to proceed –
a decision that for whatever reason – is open to
challenge
‘Someone shows me the
complexes B and I say “ they are not proofs of the equations A”. Then he says:
“You haven’t seen the system on which the complexes are constructed”, and
points it out to me. How can that make Bs into proofs?’
the arguments of the
complexes are propositional games –
a game is not a proof –
and furthermore this notion
of proof is not logical –
proof is a rhetorical
notion
the integrity of an
equation – if that is what is really at
issue here –
rests in the rules
governing its formation and action
‘This insight makes me
ascend to another, a higher level; whereas a proof would have to be carried out at a lower level.’
any proposal – complex or
not – is open –
open to proposal
there is only one level in
propositional reality –
and all proposals – all
propositions are equal –
all propositions are open
to question – open to doubt – uncertain –
we begin with a proposal –
and we propose in relation to it
‘Nothing but a definite
transition to an equation from other equations is a proof of that equation.
Here there is no such thing, and nothing else can do anything to make B into a
proof of A.’
a definite transition to an
equation from other equation – is a step in a game –
you transition from one
proposition to another – in any context – as of course we do constantly –
where’s the proof?
what goes for ‘proof’ – is
a back story enforced with rhetoric
‘But can’t I say that if I
have proved this about A, I have
proved A? Wherever did I get the illusion that by doing this I had proved it?
There must surely be some deep reason for this’
let me put the proposal
that the ‘deep reason for this’ – is fear
fear of uncertainty –
and really an intellectual
– and hence emotional – and hence behavioral –
cowering
fear of uncertainty is fear
of the logical reality – of reality – as it is proposed
fear of uncertainty comes
out of a lack of courage
the courage required – to
embrace logic
‘Well, if it is an
illusion, at all events it arose from our expression in word-language “this
proposition holds for all numbers”; for on this view the algebraic proposition
is only another way of writing the proposition of word-language. And that form
of expression caused us to confuse the case of all the numbers with the case of
‘all the people in this room’. (What we do to distinguish the cases is to ask:
how does one verify the one and the other?)’
is the algebraic
proposition only another way of writing the proposition of word-language?
propositions are translated
from one form to another – and the difference is uncertainty –
this goes on all the time
however a proposition of
one form – i.e. word language – is not
a proposition of another form – i.e. mathematical / algebraic
different forms – different
contexts – different functions –
all open to question – to
doubt – all uncertain
‘this proposition holds for
all numbers’ – is a proposal – open
to question – to doubt – uncertain –
‘all the people in this
room’ – strikes me as an incomplete sentence – ‘all the people in this room …’
– what? – i.e. what about them? –
so do we or don’t we have a
proposal here? – I suppose we do
still it’s a bit of a
floater
‘how does one verify the
one and the other? –
is verification the issue?
‘this proposition holds for
all numbers’ –
do we start checking all
numbers against the proposition?
well that would be an
endless task – and what then of verification?
isn’t the issue – how is the proposition used – in what
contexts does it function?
perhaps ‘this proposition
holds for all numbers’ – is used as a rule? –
you have to know where it
comes from – and how it is used – to have a go at assessing it
and as for ‘all the people
in this room’ –
I suppose you could do a
count –
and in that case you play a
propositional game – the addition game
games are played
they are not verified
‘If I suppose the functions
j, y,
F exactly defined and then write the schema for the inductive proof:
R
µ j(1) = y(1) A
B b j(c
+ 1) = F{j(c)}
} … jn
= yn
g y(c + 1) = F{y(c)
Even then I can’t say that the step from jr
to yr
is taken on the basis of r (if the step
µ, b g was made in accordance with r – in particular
cases r = µ). It is
still the equation A it is made in accordance with, and I can only say that it
corresponds to the complex B if I regard that as another sign in place of the
equation A.
For of course
the schema for the step had to include µ, b g.
In fact R
isn’t the schema for the inductive proof BIII; that is much more
complicated, since it has to include the schema BI.’
the inductive
argument – ‘the schema for the inductive proof’ – is best seen as an accepted
practice of procedure –
and that I am
afraid is all any kind of ‘proof’
amounts to
steps ‘made
in accordance with’ – amounts to ‘careful speculation’ within a given
propositional framework
complex B as
another sign in place of the equation A? –
yes you can
propose alternative signs but really what is the point?
all that is
relevant is the equation
‘The only time it is advisable to call something a
‘proof’ is when the ordinary grammar of the word ‘proof’ doesn’t accord with
the grammar of that object under consideration.’
isn’t this to say that a proof is a proof when it
can’t be a proof?
that is when its grammar can’t or doesn’t
correspond with the grammar of that to be proved
so there’s no proof?
or there is proof but it doesn’t correspond with
anything that needs to be proved?
strange notion
‘there is no proof ‘– is the best way to put it –
and is the fact of it
‘What causes the profound uneasiness is in the last
analysis a tiny but obvious feature of the traditional expression.’
perhaps the point here is that we just
automatically assume that mathematical propositions are subject to the question
of proof
if you are profoundly uneasy about this – that is
good –
it’s a step in the right direction
the mathematical proposition – as with any
proposition – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
the idea of ‘proof’ runs quite contrary to the
nature of the proposition –
‘proof’ is a rhetorical notion
mathematical propositions have integrity – not in terms of any rhetorical deception – but rather
in terms of the rules – the accepted propositional practice – that govern their
construction and use
all we have in human affairs is proposals – and
differing uses of proposals –
beyond that there is nothing
‘What does it mean, that R justifies a step of the
form A? No doubt it means that I have decided to allow in my calculus only
steps in accordance with a schema B in which the propositions µ, b, g, are
derivable in accordance with r (And of course that would
only mean that I allowed only the steps AI, AII etc., and
that those had schemata B corresponding to them).
It would be
better to write “and the schemata had the form R corresponding to them”. The
sentence added in brackets was intended to say that the appearance of
generality – I mean the generality of the concept of the inductive method – is
unnecessary, for in the end it only amounts to the fact that the particular
constructions BI, BII, etc. are constructed flanking the
equations AI, AII, etc. Or that in that case it is
superfluous to pick out the common feature of the constructions; all that is
relevant are the constructions themselves, for there is nothing there except these proofs, and the concept under
which these proofs fall is superfluous, because we never made any use of it.
Just as if I only want to say – pointing to three objects – “put that and that
and that in my room”, the concept chair is superfluous even though the three
objects are chairs. (And if they aren’t suitable furniture for sitting on, that
won’t be changed by someone’s drawing attention to a similarity between them).
But that only means the individual proof needs our acceptance of it as such (if
‘proof’ is to mean what it means); and if it doesn’t have it no discovery of an
analogy with other such constructions can give it to it. The reason why it
looks like a proof is that
µ, b, g and A are equations, and that a general rule
can be given, according to which we can construct (and in that sense derive) A
from B.
After the event we may become aware of this general rule. (But does that make us aware that the Bs are
really proofs of A?) What we may become aware of is a rule we might have
started with and which in conjunction with µ would have
enabled us to construct AI, AII, etc. But no one would
have called it a proof in this game.’
‘all that is
relevant is the constructions themselves’ –
yes
‘for there is
nothing there except these proofs, and the concept under which these proofs
fall is superfluous’ –
yes the
concept is superfluous – except in a rhetorical sense
as for the
proofs –
‘But that
only means the individual proof needs our acceptance of it as such’
yes the key
term here is ‘acceptance’ –
and this
acceptance – is the acceptance of the proposition
the so called
‘proof’ – is no more than a vehicle for
the acceptance
‘(if ‘proof’
is to mean what it means)’ –
yes well –
what it means – in my opinion comes down to bad (foundational) epistemology – and
corrupt logic –
or it means –
just what mathematicians do – how they behave
‘and that a
general rule can be given, according to which we can construct (and in that
sense derive) A from B’
yes this is a
rule governed propositional activity –
which in this
case is a propositional game
‘After the event we may become aware of
this general rule. (But does that
make us aware that the Bs are really proofs of A?) What we may become aware of
is a rule we might have started with and which in conjunction with µ would have enabled us to construct AI, AII,
etc. But no one would have called it a proof in this game.’
yes – well put
‘Whence the conflict: “That
isn’t a proof!” “That surely isn’t a proof.”?’
‘whence the conflict?’ –
really? –
any proposal put – in any
context – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
that is the nature of
(human) propositions
I say “today it was hot” –
you say “no it wasn’t” –
no great mystery –
it is everyday
propositional reality –
the idea of proof is to try
and kill off question – doubt – uncertainty –
to kill off reality
it really all gets back to
Plato’s delusion – and his failure to face up to and to deal with propositional
reality –
and we have all paid a
great price for his eloquence –
for his rhetoric
‘We might say that it is
doubtless true, that in proving B by µ I use µ to trace the contours of the equation A, but
not in the way I call “proving A by µ”.’
yes different
games of acceptance
‘The
difficulty that needs to be overcome in these discussions is the difficulty of
looking at the proof by induction as something new, naively as it were.’
the
‘inductive proof’ as with any ‘proof’ facilitates
acceptance –
perhaps the
value of any induction just is that it always leaves a question – a doubt –
uncertainty
induction is
a methodology that gives us action in the face of uncertainty –
and in that
sense it can be seen to be a logical representation of propositional reality
I don’t think
uncertainty is naïve – in fact just the opposite –
uncertainty
as the end of naivety
‘So when we said above we
could begin with R, this beginning with R is in a way a piece of humbug. It
isn’t like beginning a calculation by working out 526 x 718. For in the latter
case setting out the problem is the first step on the journey to the solution.
But in the former case I
immediately drop the R and have to begin again somewhere else. And when it
turns out that I construct a complex of the form R, it is again immaterial
whether I explicitly set it out earlier, since setting it out hasn’t helped me
at all mathematically, i.e. in the calculus. So what is left is just that I now
have a complex of the form of R in front of me.’
yes the ritual of R
‘We might imagine we were
acquainted only with the proof of BI and could then say: all we have
is this construction – no mention of analogy between this and other
constructions, or of a general principle in carrying out the constructions. –
If I then see B and A like this I am bound to ask: but why do you call that a
proof of A precisely? – (I am not asking: why do you call it a proof of A)! Any reply will have to
make me aware of the relation between A and B which is expressed in V.’
‘why do you call that a proof of A?’ –
yes – you might see in the
so called ‘proof’ – a path to A – even some sort of an approximation of A –
propositional packaging for A –
but proof?
a proof is either internal
to a proposition – or external to it –
if the former – then there
is really nothing of consequence to be said – you just get on with it
if the latter – how can a different proposal do anything here –
but be used to endorse the subject
proposition?
and if so proof comes down
to – endorsement – acceptance
yes you can put up a
definition of the relation between A and B – the idea of V – and go from there
–
still in all – that amounts
to – acceptance – affirmation – of A
and so the term ‘proof’ is
just a signal of this – a signal of
acceptance
in the end – regardless of
whatever propositional constructions are impressed on the issue – regardless of
what arguments are developed and used –
that is regardless of your
conception of proof –
‘proof’ has no more logical
status than a nod of the head –
and as to all the work done
on ‘proofs’ –
interesting as that might
be – brilliant as it might be –
just ritual
nevertheless – that is the
way of it –
how the game is in fact
played
‘Someone shoes us BI and
explains to us the relationship with AI, that is, that the right
side of A was obtained in such and such a manner etc. etc. We understand him;
and he asks us: is that a proof of A? Certainly not!
Had we understood
everything there was to understand about the proof? Had we seen the general
form of the connection between A and B? Yes!
We might also infer from
that that in this way we can construct a B from every A and therefore conversely an A from every B as
well.’
someone explains the
relationship – is – someone proposes
a relationship
is that a proof? –
if that is to ask – is that
proposal – a guarantee of the
integrity of A?
the answer in general terms
is no –
and the reason is that any
proposal is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain –
a ‘guarantee’ defies logic
– it is a creature of pretence and rhetoric
on the other hand – if by
proof – what you mean – is that a proposal of proof is a good reason to proceed
with A –
well that may or may not be
the case –
it all depends on who you
are proposing to and how they regard your proposal –
here we are deep in
contingency
‘we can construct a B from
every A and therefore conversely an A
from every B as well.’ –
ok – a game proposal – a
propositional game – why not – if you have nothing better to do?
‘The proof is constructed
on a definite plan (a plan used to construct other proofs as well). But this
plan cannot make the proof a proof. For all we have here is one of the
embodiments of the plan, and we can altogether disregard the plan as a general
concept. The proof has to speak for itself and the plan is only embodied in it,
it isn’t itself a constituent part of the proof. (That is what I have been
wanting to say all the time). Hence it is no use to me if someone draws my
attention to the similarity between proofs in order to convince me that they
are proofs.’
if the proof is constructed
on a definite plan – but the plan cannot make the proof a proof –
what’s the point of the
definite plan? –
is it a definite plan not
to make a proof?
‘The proof has to speak for
itself and the plan is only embodied in it, it isn’t itself a constituent part
of the proof’ –
the proof speaks for
itself?
I would say the proposition
(to be ‘proved’) – speaks for itself –
and the ‘proof’ – speaks
for the proposition –
which if the proposition
speaks for itself –
is hardly necessary
and the plan embodied in
the proof – isn’t a constituent part of the proof?
the plan is in the proof –
but not in the proof?
and wasn’t the original
point that the proof was in the plan ‘constructed on a definite plan’?
so what’s it to be – the
proof is in the plan – or the plan is in the proof?
I don’t think we have a
plan here – or a proof
‘Isn’t our principle: not
to use a concept-word where one isn’t necessary? – That means, in cases where
the concept-word really stands for an
enumeration, to say so.’
any action proposed will be
defined conceptually –
so the concept-word – is
not the action – but an understanding of it
enumeration you would say
is the action –
its understanding – in a
propositional context – is a conceptual matter
‘When I said earlier “that
isn’t a proof” I meant ‘proof’ in an already established sense according to
which it can be gathered from A and B by themselves. In this sense I can say: I
understand perfectly well what B does and what relationship it has to A; all
further information is superfluous and what is there isn’t a proof. In this
sense I am concerned only with A and B; I don’t see anything beyond them and
nothing else concerns me.’
‘according to which it can
be gathered from A and B themselves’ –
‘gathered’ – amounts to
anything and nothing
if you understand the
relationship – the relationship is proposed –
if there is no proposal –
there is no relationship
‘In this sense I am
concerned only with A and B; I don’t see anything beyond them and nothing else
concerns me.’
the point is that if you
see ‘A and B’ – you see a
relationship –
the proposal of the
relationship is – ‘something beyond
them’
I understand Wittgenstein
here on proof – but just because you throw out ‘proof’ – or a particular
version of it – doesn’t mean – that you throw out all and any propositions
regarding A and B
the question for
Wittgenstein is –‘what is it you see?’
‘If I do this, I can see
clearly enough the relationship in accordance with the rule V, but it doesn’t
enter into my head to use it as an expedient in construction. If someone told
me while I was considering B and A that there is a rule according to which we
could have constructed B from A (or conversely), I could only say to him “don’t
bother me with irrelevant trivialities.” Because of course it’s something that’s
obvious, and I see immediately that it doesn’t make B a proof of A. For the
general rule couldn’t show that B is a proof of A and not of some other proposition, unless it were a proof in the
first place. That means, that the fact that the connection between A and B is
in accordance with a rule can’t show that B is a proof of A. Any and every
connection could be used as a construction of B from A (and conversely).’
I agree with Wittgenstein
that the idea of proof – an argument for epistemological foundation – fails –
not because I think it is
obvious – but rather because such a notion flies in the face of propositional
logic
a proposition – a proposal
– any proposal – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
if you are after certainty
in any form – what you are dealing with – what you are looking for is prejudice
and the idea of the claim
of the obvious – just is that you can’t argue against it –
and that of course is
rubbish
proof is rhetoric – and
really we need more than rhetoric – to make the point –
Wittgenstein hasn’t
delivered
‘So when I said “R
certainly isn’t used for the construction, so we have no concerns with it” I
should have said: I am only concerned with A and B. It is enough if I confront
A and B with each other and ask: “is B a proof of A?” So I don’t need to
construct A from B according to a previously established rule; it is sufficient
for me to place the particular As – however many there are – in confrontation
with particular Bs. I don’t need a previously established construction rule (a
rule needed to obtain the As).’
yes – the construction of A
from B – a propositional game –
if that’s what you call
‘proof’ – why not?
and so you run with a
‘previously established construction rule’ – if that’s how you do it – where’s
the problem?
‘confront A with B’ –
‘place the particular As in confrontation with particular Bs’ –
ok – but ‘confrontation’
means what?
if you just want to do – with no account – I say – fair
enough –
but there is no explanation
here –
and don’t pretend that
there is
I am all for the sharp
focus on A and B – and as for construction that train has left the station when
it comes to dealing the relationship of A and B –
as to the relationship – it
may be – at least initially – a matter of speculation – but as that matter is
thrashed out – the question will be – what rule applies here – in this context?
so be clear – it is not as
if the A and B on the page – are all there is to the focus –
the central focus is the
relationship –
and that will come down to
– the rule that governs their relationship
without this you have
virtually nothing – just signs on a page – no action
and also –
if you are not prepared to
state – articulate – propose – that relationship
how do you know that there
is one?
how do you know what you
are doing?
all very well to say you do
–
but that is hardly enough
if you are working in a rule governed propositional discipline –
where – as a matter of fact
– as a matter of practice –
there are standards and
issues of accountability
playing the ‘seer’ just
doesn’t work
‘What I mean is: in
Skolem’s calculus we don’t need any
such concept, the list is sufficient.
Nothing is lost if instead
of saying “we have proved the fundamental laws A in this fashion” we merely show
that we can co-ordinate with them constructions that resemble them in certain
respects.’
‘we have proved the
fundamental laws A in this fashion’ – is just rhetoric –
and I would say that
learning that you can do without such rhetoric – or at least minimizing its
use – is to be recommended –
and I would suggest leads
to a clearer sharper understanding
if such rhetoric is
understood for what it is – just ‘propositional packaging’ –
and is not taken seriously
– perhaps seen as an instance of a propositional tradition and ritual – then it
is quite harmless
the real game is the propositional action taken –
how that is packaged up is
by and large irrelevant to the game –
still it needs to be called
out for what it is and checked with a critical eye –
reason being – it can
distract from the main game – and it might just send some epistemological
innocent – off on the wrong track –
bullshit can be harmless –
but it is bullshit
as to –
‘we merely show that we can
co-ordinate with them constructions that resemble them in certain respects.’
yes that’s about it
‘The concept of generality
(and of recursion) used in these proofs has no greater generality than can be
read immediately from the proofs’
these ‘proofs’ are language
games
the concepts are employed
in these games
and these concepts of
generality and recursion may have application in other propositional actions
and games
‘The bracket } in R, which
unites µ, b and g can’t mean anymore than that we regard the
step in A (or a step of the form A) as justified if the terms (sides) of the
steps are related to each other in the ways characterized by the schema B. B
then takes the place of A. And just as before we said: the step is permitted in
my calculus if it corresponds to one of the As, so we now say: it is permitted
if it corresponds to one of the Bs.
But that
wouldn’t mean we had gained any simplification or reduction.’
B takes the
place of A –
a move – a
step – from – one language game to another –
a
simplification or reduction?
I think it is
rather that B and A are different propositional
games –
and that a
step (an argument) has been made from one to the other –
that’s the
proposal
‘We are given
the calculus of equations. In that calculus “proof” has a fixed meaning. If I
now call the inductive calculation a proof, it isn’t a proof that saves me
checking whether the steps in the chain of equations have been taken in
accordance with these
particular
rules (or paradigms). If they have been, I say that the last equation of the chain
is proved, or that the chain of equations is correct.’
yes – exactly
right –
‘proof’ – if
it is to have any functional meaning just is
– the action of a rule governed
procedure
‘Suppose that
we were using the first method to check the calculation (a + b)3 = …
and at the
first step someone said: “yes, that step was certainly taken in accordance with
a (b + c) = a . b + a . c, but is that right?” And then we showed him the
inductive derivation of that equation. –‘
different methods –
different arguments – different games
‘The question “Is the
equation G right?” means in one meaning: can it be derived in accordance with
the paradigms? – In the other case it means: can the equations
µ, b and g be derived in accordance with the paradigm
(or paradigms?) – and here we have put two meanings of the question (or of the “proof”) on the same level
(expressed them in a single system) and can now compare them (and see that they
are not the same).’
yes different paradigms –
different methods – different practices – different understandings of ‘proof’
‘And indeed the new proof
doesn’t give you what you might expect: it doesn’t base the calculus on a
smaller foundation – as happens if we replace the p v q and ~p by p|q, or reduce the number of
axioms, or something similar. For if we now say that all the basic equations A
have been derived from r alone, the word “derived”
here means something quite different. (After this promise we expect the big
links in the chain to be replaced by smaller ones, not by two half links.) And
in one sense these derivations leave everything as it was. For in the new
calculus the links in the old one essentially continue to exist as links. The
old structure is not taken to pieces.
So we have to say the proof goes on in the same way as before. And in the old sense the irreducibility remains.’
what we are
considering here is different constructions –
different calculi – different methods – different ‘proofs’ –
yes – you can
argue that one calculus can be accounted for by another –
and that
therefore –
‘in the new
calculus the links in the old one essentially continue to exist as links. The
old structure is not taken to pieces.
So we have to say the proof goes on in the same way as before. And in the old sense the irreducibility remains.’
and what then
does it come down to?
one might be
tempted to say it’s a question of style –
or perhaps at
a deeper level – philosophical orientation –
which amounts
to what?
and the
answer here could be anything –
anything you
want to propose
what we can
say – as an empirical fact – is that we have different practices –
different
practices – whose validation just is
practice –
and that the
idea of the reduction or translation of one practice to another – is trivial –
best to
embrace the multiplicity
Oakum would
not favor this –
‘plurality
ought never be posed without necessity’ –
I say here –
the issue is not necessity – it is propositional practice – propositional
reality
‘So we can’t
say that Skolem has put the algebraic system on a smaller foundation, for he
hasn’t given it foundations in the same sense as is used in algebra.’
well yes we
are dealing with different conceptions –
of course
comparisons will be made –
but is there
much to this?
(the old
chestnut – ‘does size matter?’)
different
calculi – and different understandings –
different
world views
the common
ground is what we don’t know – not
what we do
the common
ground is what is not proposed –
not what is
‘In the inductive proof
doesn’t µ show a connection between
the As? And doesn’t this show we are here concerned with proofs? – The
connection shown is not the one that breaking up the A steps into r steps would establish. And one connection between the As is already
visible before any proof.’
firstly – this notion of proof –
is – if it is anything – is open to question – open
to doubt – is – uncertain
and if so – how is it in any sense different to any
other proposal – any other proposition?
secondly –
I think proof is best understood as satisfaction –
satisfaction that the game is properly constructed and that it is
played in accordance with its rules –
however that is then interpreted and represented –
and of course – again – satisfaction – as we all
know – is a matter – open to question –
open to doubt – is uncertain
thirdly –
now if your
notion of proof is deductive – then unless – you are open to a propositional –
conceptual – philosophical – diversity –
an ‘inductive
proof’ – will make no sense to you – (and visa versa)
and an
inductive methodology – or paradigm – will be regarded as illegitimate
and there
really is no argument that will sway someone who cannot see beyond their own
conception and practice –
what you are
up against here is prejudice – intellectual prejudice
the empirical
reality is diversity –
and this
empirical reality is a reflection of (or indeed – reflected in) – the logical –
that is – propositional – reality –
the reality
of the proposal – as the basis of our
thought feeling and action –
the proposal
as open to question – open to doubt – as uncertain
prejudice
flies in the face of uncertainty –
uncertainty
flies in the face of prejudice
against
prejudice all you can do is put that any proposal – any proposition – just
simply is – open to question –
and make the
point that what goes on in this world – the world we live in – is diverse
that should
be a straightforward empirical matter –
a simple
observation
‘I can write
the rule R like this:
a + (1 + 1) = (a + 1) + 1 ½
a + (x + 1) (a + x) + 1 ½ S
a + ((x + 1) + 1) (a +(x + 1)) = 1 ½
or like this:
a + (b +1) = (a + b) + 1
if I take R or S as a
definition or substitute for that form.
If I then say that the
steps in accordance with the rule R are justified thus:
µ a + (b + !) = (a + b) + 1
b a + (b +(c +1) = a + (b + c) = 1) = (a +
(b + c)) + 1 } B
g (a + b) + (c + 1) = ((a +b) + c) + 1
you can
reply: “If that’s what you call a justification, then you have justified the steps.
But you haven’t told us any more than if you had just drawn our attention to
the rule R and its formal relationship to µ (or to µ, b, and g).”
So I might
also have said: I take the rule R in such and such a way as a paradigm for my
steps.
Suppose now
that Skolem, following his proof of the associative law, takes the step to:
a + 1 = 1 + a
a = (b + 1) = (a + b) =
1 } C
(b + 1) + a =
b + (1 +a) = b + (a +1) = (b + a) + 1
If he says the first and
third steps in the third line are justified according to the already proved
associative law, that tells us no more than if he said the steps were taken in
accordance with the paradigm a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c (i.e. they correspond to
the paradigm) and a schema µ, b, g was derived by steps according to the
paradigm µ. –
But does B
justify these steps, or not?” “What do you mean by the word ‘justify’? – “Well
the step is justified if a theorem has been proved that holds for all numbers”
– But in what case would that have happened? What do you call a proof that a
theorem holds for all cardinal numbers? How do you know that a theorem is valid
for all cardinal numbers, since you can’t test it? Your only criterion is the proof itself. So you can stipulate a form and call it the form of the proof that a
proposition holds for all cardinal numbers. In that case we really gain nothing
by being first shown the
general form
of these proofs; for that doesn’t show that the individual proof really gives
us what we want from it; because I mean, it doesn’t justify the proof or
demonstrate
that it is a proof of a theorem for all cardinal numbers. Instead the recursive
proof has to be its own justification. If we really want to justify our proof
procedure as a proof of a generalization of this kind, we do something
different: we give a series of examples and then we are satisfied by the
examples and the law we recognize in them, and we say: yes our proof really
gives us what we want. But we must remember that by giving this series of
examples we have only translated the notations B and C into a different
notation. (For the series of examples is not an incomplete application of the
general form, but another expression of the law.) An explanation in word-language
of the proof (of what it proves) only translates the proof into another form of
expression: because of this we can drop the explanation altogether. And if we
do so, the mathematical relationships become much clearer, no longer obscured
by the equivocal expressions of word-language. For example, if I put B right
beside A, without interposing any expression of word-language like
‘for all
cardinal numbers, etc.” then the misleading appearance of a proof of A by B
cannot arise. We then see quite soberly how far the relationships between B and
A and a + b = b + a extend and where they stop. Only thus do we learn the real
structure
and important
features of that relationship, and escape the confusion caused by the form of
word-language, which makes everything uniform.’
what do you
mean by the word ‘justify’?
‘well the
step is justified if a theorem has been proved that holds for all cardinal
numbers’ –
and if your
only criterion is the proof itself –
then
justification is what?
asserting –
or affirming the proof –
and the proof
is really what – an affirmation of the proposition?
so why the
need for the so called ‘proof’ – isn’t it just a reaffirmation of the
proposition?
the idea of
the proof is to give backing to the affirmation of the proposition –
but what
backing can you give to affirmation?
you either
affirm a proposition or you don’t – you get on with the job at hand – or you
don’t
reaffirmation adds nothing here
so
justification comes out as – affirmation of the proof – and proof as –
reaffirmation of the proposition
reaffirmation
(proof) can of course go on indefinitely –
and so you
ask – what is the point of the proof?
can I suggest
a grammatical analogy here?
what I have
in mind is that proof is like – has the same function as – a full stop in word-language grammar
yes we can go
on forever – affirming – reaffirming –
but we are
not going to – and we don’t want to –
and the idea
of doing so actually destroys the enterprise
we have to bring our argument to an end
and the ‘have to’ here – is a pragmatic ‘have to’
so – what we know as proof – the process of proof –
is best seen as the ritual developed to bring argument to a stop – to an
end
and as with any ritual – it requires adherence –
without adherence – there is no game
even so – the point remains that the ritual of
proof is nothing more than rhetoric –
the proposition is put – you can affirm it or deny
it –
you can play the game or not play the game –
the need
for proof – just indicates propositional
insecurity –
and as to that – propositional insecurity – only
exists if you believe in propositional security
now there is no such thing
it takes some courage to recognise and accept that
any proposition – any proposal – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
but if you do accept this –
what is there to be insecure about?
embrace the uncertainty – work in it and with it –
recognise it as the mark of intellectual freedom –
indeed of freedom
understand that each proposal – each proposition –
is not a dead truth – but rather a field of possibility
Wittgenstein goes on to say –
that if we really want to justify our proof
procedure of a generalization of this kind –
we give a series of examples – and then we are
satisfied by the examples and the law we recognize in them –
and then we say – yes our proof really gives us
what we want
which is what? – proof –
our proof gives us proof
this tells us nothing
it is clear that what proof amounts to – is affirmation of the proposition
and the various props brought into play – i.e.
examples – laws – explanations etc. –
are expressions
of that affirmation
do we need proofs – their translations and
explanations – to affirm propositions?
no – a proposition can be affirmed and proceeded
with – without proofs – that is without reaffirmation
–
proofs may be rhetorically useful – but they are
not logically relevant –
they are not relevant to the action of mathematics
they are just shadows
I am not
suggesting that mathematicians no longer engage in the proof-game
I am only
saying that it should be seen for what it is –
a shadow-play
as to
propositional generalization in mathematics –
the
generalization functions as a ground or space for speculation –
it opens up
possibilities –
i.e. the
possibility of recursion – recursive games
and if
understood correctly – generalization sets the scene for a mathematics – that
literally flies in the face of the earthbound notion of proof
‘Here we see first and foremost that we are interested in
the tree of the structures B, C etc., and that in it is visible on all sides,
like a particular kind of branching, the following form
j(1) =
y(1)
j(n
+ 1) = F(jn)
y(n
+ 1) = F(yn)
These forms turn up in different arrangements and
combinations but they are not elements of the construction in the same sense as
the paradigms in the proof of
(a + (b + (c + 1))) = (a + (b +c)) + 1 or (a + b)2
= a2 + 2ab + b2. The aim of the “recursive proofs” is of
course to connect the algebraic calculus with the calculus of numbers. And the
tree of the recursive proofs doesn’t “justify” the algebraic calculus unless
that is supposed to mean that it connects it with the arithmetical one. It
doesn’t justify it in the sense in which the list of paradigms justifies the
algebraic calculus, i.e. the steps in it.’
no it doesn’t – the list of paradigms illustrates the algebraic calculus –
the tree of recursive proofs – makes use of the algebraic calculus and its connection with the
arithmetical one –
it places the algebraic calculus in a new context
and there is no ‘justification’ – apart from use
‘So tabulating the paradigms for the steps makes sense in
the cases where we are interested in showing that such and such transformations
are all made by means of those transition forms, arbitrarily chosen as they
are. But it doesn’t make sense where the calculation is to be justified in a
another sense, where mere looking at calculation – independently of any
comparison with a table of previously established norms – must shew us whether
we are to allow it or not. Skolem did not have to promise us any proof of the
associative and commutative laws; he could simply have said he would show us a
connection between paradigms of algebra and the calculation rules of
arithmetic. But isn’t this hair-splitting? Hasn’t he reduced the number of
paradigms? Hasn’t he, for instance replaced [e]very pair of laws with a single
one, namely, a + (b + 1) = (a + b) + 1? No. When we prove e.g. (a + b)4
= etc. (k) we can while doing so make use of the previously proved proposition
(a = b)2 = etc. (1). But in
that case the steps in k which are justified by 1 can also be justified by the
rules used to prove 1. And the relation of 1 to those first rules is the same
as that of a sign introduced to the primary signs used to define it; we can
always eliminate the definitions and go back to the primary signs. But when we
take a step in C that is justified by B, we can’t take the same step with a +
(b + 1) = (a + b) + 1 alone. What is called proof here doesn’t break a step in
to smaller steps but does something quite different.’
‘mere looking’ – is that supposed to be some kind of
justification?
and ‘whether we are allowed it or not’?
the issue is function –
and there is no certainty here –
at best – we use what is at hand – and recognizable in the
practice – and here we are talking about the rules – the games of calculation
there can always be argument regarding the practice – how
the rules are interpreted –
how the calculation games are interpreted – and in whatever (mathematical) context –
large or small
and context – itself – of course – is open to question –
open to doubt – is uncertain
the question ultimately is that of use – that is the game –
do you go with it or not?
yes or no –
questions remain
‘Hasn’t he reduced the number of paradigms? Hasn’t he, for
instance replaced (e)very pair of laws with a single one, namely, a + (b + 1) =
(a + b) + 1? No.’
look – I think the question of paradigms here – do we have
more or less? – is rather pointless –
I don’t think it bears on the mathematical action –
it’s a background issue – a question of explanation –
which I think in the end is a matter of style
34 The
recursive proof does not reduce the number of fundamental laws
‘So here we don’t have a case where a group of
fundamental laws is proved by a smaller set while everything else in the proofs
remains the same. (Similarly in a system of fundamental concepts nothing is
altered in the later development if we use definitions to reduce the number of
fundamental concepts.)
(Incidentally, how very dubious is the analogy
between “fundamental laws” and “fundamental concepts”!)’
we are dealing with different laws – different proofs – nothing else
how dubious is the analogy between fundamental laws
and fundamental concepts?
what is ‘dubious’ – to say the least – is this
notion of ‘fundamental’
fundamental this or fundamental that is just
rhetorical rubbish –
the point of the notion of ‘fundamental’ – is to
‘establish’ an authority –
the only ‘authority’ – is authorship –
and the authorship of a proposal – a proposition –
is logically irrelevant –
yes – in any propositional enterprise – we start –
start somewhere – start with a proposal –
and disciplined propositional practises such as
mathematics –
as a matter of practice will have base propositions
– or propositions that can be so regarded –
and the practice will be that such propositions are
seen to be essential to the practice – or characteristic of the practice –
how this comes about is really a question for the
history of the development of the practice –
and as Wittgenstein’s ‘argument’ here shows – the
status of any such base proposal – is
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
clearly there is no ‘fundamental’ proposition – if
by that is meant – a proposition – a proposal – that is beyond question –
beyond doubt – a proposition that is certain
what we can say is that different propositional
practices – are different –
that is the empirical / logical reality
this point applies as much to Skolem’s argument as
it does to Wittgenstein’s
Wittgenstein half gets this – but is reluctant or
unable to grasp the broader logical implication of uncertainty
the question for the working mathematician – if
there is a question for him or her here – is – which propositional arrangement
– or propositional argument will – under circumstances – be useful?
i.e. what am I going to use to get to where I am
looking to go?
now – again – there will be no certainty here –
we play games with established propositional models
–
or we develop new models for new games –
and if we argue for a new proposal – a new game –
we hope we can attract some players – it’s as basic as that
‘It is something like this: all that the proof of a
ci-deviant fundamental proposition
does is to continue the system of proofs backwards. But the recursive proofs
don’t continue backwards the system of algebraic proofs (with the old
fundamental laws); they are a new system, that seems only to run parallel with
the first one.’
yes – exactly – a new – a different practice
‘It is a strange observation that in the inductive
proofs the irreducibility (independence) of the fundamental rules must show
itself after the proof no less than before. Suppose we said the same thing
about the case of the normal proofs (or definitions), where fundamental rules
are further reduced, and a new relationship between them is discovered (or
constructed).’
yes – the ‘inductive proof’ here becomes what? – an
illustration – an approximation – a representation – some kind of picture of
the ‘fundamental’ rules –
however you represent – the so called proof – is
effectively irrelevant – irrelevant if you hold to the rules
as to definitions – the same applies – you either
accept – and work with them – or they are of no use –
playing around with them – ‘reducing’ – and
constructing new relations – might be an interesting thing to do – might lead
to new ways of seeing and doing – but it is not affirming and then working with
the definitions – it’s not – as it were getting on with the job
‘If I am right that the independence remains intact
after the recursive proof, that sums up everything I have to say against the
recursive “proof”’
this is to say that the recursive proof is in fact
irrelevant –
ok – but this is an argument not just in regard to
‘recursive proof’ – but to any proof
it applies to the whole ‘proof enterprise’ –
to all and any of its production lines
‘The inductive proof doesn’t break up the step in
A. Isn’t it that that makes me baulk at calling it a proof? It’s that that
tempts me to say that whatever it does – even if it is constructed by R and µ – it can’t do more than show something about the step.’
it really just states that the step is made –
and you can ask – do we really need any such
statement? –
really what logical purpose does it serve?
isn’t it just a piece of rhetorical flourish?
‘If we imagine a mechanism constructed from
cogwheels made simply out of uniform wedges held together by a ring, it is
still the cogwheels that remain in a certain sense the units of the mechanism.’
yes – you can indeed describe the mechanism this
way –
however it is not the only valid description –
‘the cogwheels as units’ – is a focus –
a focus that will serve certain purposes – it is not
the only possible focus
the action
of the mechanism – could well be the primary focus
the mechanism – the entity– in the absence of
description – any description –
logically speaking – is an unknown –
we make known in
proposal –
and any proposal – is open to question – open to
doubt – is uncertain
the ground of proposal – is the unknown –
at best our proposals – suit our purposes – our
uses
‘It is like this: if the barrel is made of hoops
and wattles, it is these, combined as they are (as a complex) that hold the
liquid and form new units as containers’
yes you can explain the barrel in these terms –
however it is quite clear that for certain uses the
barrel may not be regarded as a complex – but rather as a simple – as a unit
the barrel can be variously described
that is the fact of it – the logical / empirical
reality
‘Imagine a chain consisting of links which each can
be replaced by two smaller ones. Anything which is anchored by the chain can
also be anchored by smaller links instead of by the large ones. But we might
also imagine every link in the chain being made of two parts, each perhaps
shaped like half a ring, which together formed a link, but could not
individually be used as links.
Then it wouldn’t mean at all the same to say, on
the one hand: the anchoring done by the large links can be done entirely by
small links – and on the other hand; the anchoring can be done entirely by half
the links. What is the difference?
One proof replaces a chain with large links by a
chain with small links, the other shows how one can put together the old large
links from several parts.
The similarity as well as the difference between
the two cases is obvious.
Of course the comparison between the proof and the
chain is a logical comparison and therefore a completely exact expression of
what it illustrates.’
yes – what we have here is different descriptions – different valid descriptions
the proof is a description of the chain – or the
chain a description of the proof
and ‘an expression of what it illustrates’ – is ‘an
illustration of what is expressed’ –
what we have here without the mumbo jumbo – is a proposal –
and the proposal will be ‘exact’ – to the extent
that it is not subjected to question – to doubt –
‘exactness’ – is really just a rhetorical cover –
that has no logical significance –
in certain propositional rituals – the description
‘exact’ amounts to propositional
satisfaction –
or the decision
to proceed
35 Recurring
decimals 1/3 = 

‘We regard the periodicity of a fraction, e.g. of
1/3 as consisting in the fact that something called the extension of the
infinite decimal contains only threes; we regard the fact that in this division
the remainder is the same as the dividend as a mere symptom of this property of the infinite extension. Or else we
correct this view by saying that it isn’t an infinite extension that has this
property, but an infinite series of finite extensions; and it is of this that the property of the
division is a symptom. We may then say: the extension taken to one term is 0.3, to two terms 0.33, to
three terms
0.333, and so on. That is the rule and the “and so
on” refers to the regularity; the rule might also be written “½0.3,
0.x,
0.x3 |”.
But what is proved by the division
1/3 = 0.3 is this regularity in
contrast to another, not regularity in contrast to
irregularity. The periodic division 1/3 =
0.3 (in contrast to 1/3 = 0.3) proves a
1 1
periodicity in the quotient, that it determines the
rule (the repetend), it lays down; it isn’t a symptom that a regularity is
“always there”. Where is it already?
In things like the particular expansions that I have written on this page. But
they aren’t “the expansions”. (Here
we are misled by the idea of unwritten ideal extensions, which are a phantasm
like those ideal, undrawn geometric straight lines of which the actual lines we
draw are mere tracings.) When I said “the ‘and so on’ refers to the regularity”
I was distinguishing it from the ‘and so on’ in “he read all the letters of the
alphabet: a, b, c and so on”. When I say “the extensions of 1/3 are 0.3, 0.33
and so on” I give three three
extensions and – a rule. That is the only thing that is infinite, and only in
the same way as the division 1/3 = 0.3
1
One can say of the sign
that
it is not an abbreviation.

And the sign “| 0.3, 0. x,
0. x3 |”
isn’t a substitute for an extension, but the undervalued sign itself; and the “
” does just as well. It should give us food
for thought, that a sign like “
” is enough
to do what we need. It isn’t a mere substitute in the calculus there are no
substitutes.


If you think that the peculiar property of the
division 1/3 = 0.3 is a symptom of the
1
periodicity of the infinite decimal fractions, or the decimal fractions of the expansion,
it is indeed a sign that something is
regular, but what? The extensions that
I have constructed? But there aren’t any others. It would be a most absurd
manner of speaking to say: the property of the division is an indication that
the result has the form “½0.a,
0.x,
0.x a½”;
that is like wanting to say that a division was an indication that the result
was a number. The sign “
” does not express its meaning from any
greater distance than “0.33 …”, because this sign gives an extension of three
terms and a rule; the extension 0.333 is inessential for our purposes and so
there remains only the rule, which is given as well by “½0.3,
0.x,
0.x3 |”.
The proposition “After the first place the division will yield the same number
to infinity”, means “The first
remainder is the same as the dividend”, just as the proposition “This
straightedge has an infinite radius” means it is straight

We might say: the places of a quotient of 1/3 are necessarily all 3s, and all that could mean would be again that the first
remainder is like the dividend and the first place of the quotient is 3. The
negation of the first proposition is therefore equivalent to the negation of
the second. So the opposite of “necessarily all” isn’t what one might call
‘accidentally all”; “necessarily all” is as it were
one word. I only have to ask: what is the criterion of the necessary
generalization, and what would be the criterion of the accidental
generalization (the criterion for all numbers accidentally having the property e)?’
‘periodicity’ is a property of a propositional game
that is a description
– of a feature – a regularity – in a mathematical game
what do we mean by ‘infinite extension’?
what it means is we are proposing – a repeatable
action with no end point
e.g. the periodicity of the fraction 1/3 consists in the
fact that the extension of the infinite decimal contains only threes –
that the remainder is the same as the dividend – is a
property of the game –
a description of its constant – a characterization of its
rule
‘and the so on’?
does it refer to the regularity of the periodicity?
the regularity just is the ‘periodicity’
the ‘and so on’ is a propositional directive –
it refers to the action of the game – which is to say – its ‘on-going-ness’
a propositional direction – and nothing more
for the game as such – by definition – can never be
completed
(are we to then say it is
not a game?
yes you could take this
line – with all the implications that follow
however it is important to
see that though we have rules to a game –
and that the rules give the
game an operational structure –
at the same time a game is
defined by its play – its actual play
so the fact is – the
practice is –
the game begins with the
start of play – and the game ends – with the end of play –
that is – when the play
stops)
‘One can say of the sign
that
it is not an abbreviation.’


‘If you think that the peculiar property of the
division 1/3 = 0.3 is a symptom of the
1
periodicity of the infinite decimal fractions, or the decimal fractions of the expansion,
it is indeed a sign that something is
regular, but what?’
is this ‘peculiar’ property (‘the remainder is the
same as the dividend’) a symptom of the periodicity?
saying that ‘the remainder is the same as the
dividend’ –
expresses the
constant of this game
so a ‘symptom’ – I suppose
yes –
if ‘symptom’ is understood
as the game (logical) constant
‘a sign that something is
regular but what?’
the periodicity is a regularity –
or ‘periodicity’ is a description of a regularity
you can play games the
principle of which is regularity – or games where the principle is irregularity
–
where the game is based on
the principle of regularity – what is regular is the action of the game –
periodicity is a form or
expression of a regularity
and as to ‘regularity’? –
an ordered (rule governed)
succession –
in short – a game
‘We might say: the places of a quotient of 1/3 are
necessarily all 3s,…’
that is the rule in play –
‘necessity’ comes out as nothing more than the game
as constructed and played –
how the game is constructed is a contingent fact
how the game is played is a contingent fact
36 The
recursive proof as a series of proofs
‘A recursive proof is the general term of a series
of proofs. So it is a law for the construction of proofs. To the question how
the general form can save me the proof of a particular proposition, e.g. 7 + (8
+ 9) = (7 + 8) + 9, the answer is that it merely gets everything ready for the
proof of the proposition, it doesn’t prove it (indeed the proposition doesn’t
occur in it). The proof consists rather of the general form plus the
proposition.’
yes – that is fair enough –
the way I would put it though is that a ‘recursive
proof’ is the general term for a series of propositional games
‘Our normal mode of expression carries the seeds of
confusion right into its foundations, because it uses the word “series” both in
the sense of “extension” and in the sense of “law”. The relationship of the two
can be illustrated by a machine for making coiled springs, in which a wire is
pushed through a helically shaped
passage to make as many coils as are desired. What is called an infinite helix
need not be anything like a finite piece of wire, or something that that
approaches the longer it becomes; it is the law of the helix, as it is embodied
in the short passage. Hence the expression “infinite helix” or “infinite
series” is misleading.’
yes – the law of the helix – is a constructive
proposal – not an operational proposal
what is termed an ‘infinite helix’ – is not a
constructive proposal – rather an operational proposal
as to ‘infinite series’ –
an ‘infinite series’ is a proposed extension –
a series is a propositional action
a series is not a law –
a series will be ‘governed’ by a law –
that is to say – ‘shaped by an over-riding
proposal’ –
and in so far as the series reflects the law –
it can be said that the law is ‘in’ the series
‘So we can always write out the recursive proof as
a limited series “and so on” without it losing any of its rigour. At the same
time this notation shows more clearly its relation to the equation A. For the
recursive proof no longer looks at all like a justification of A in the sense
of an algebraic proof – like the proof of (a + b)2. . That proof
with algebraic calculation is quite like calculation with numbers.’
we can propose a limitless series –
but we can’t write
out a limitless series –
so yes ‘we can always write out the recursive proof
as a limited series’
and it is just here that you might ask – what is
the point of proposing a limitless series?
I can only think that the value of such a proposal
– is epistemological
it makes the point that there is no end game
in practice – we operate within limitations – and
therefore we play to end games
the notion of a limitless series – keeps the game
open – logically – if not practically –
really it ushers in a different mind-set –
the ‘and so on’ indicates this
Wittgenstein here in saying that we can ‘write out
the recursive proof as a limited series and the “and so on” without losing any
of its rigour’ –
is really just suggesting we can reconcile
recursive mathematics with the algebraic form –
(and I can’t see that Wittgenstein’s view of ‘and
so on’ here – has any significance at all – it’s just a dangler)
this ‘reconciliation’ – may indeed be just what in
fact happens in mathematics – and so be it
my point is the that the recursive game and the
algebraic game – are two different
mathematical games
that one is not the other – is no cause for concern
–
we are not here defending an empire
and of course ‘the recursive proof no longer looks
at all like a justification of A in the sense of an algebraic proof’
we can forget justification – it is just a
rhetorical device – to bring consideration to an end
and the point of the ‘recursive proof’ so called –
is to indicate an on-goingness –
in so far as Skolem regarded the recursive proof as
a justification – he misrepresented it and warped it
what we have with recursion is a game that in a
sense plays itself
it does not require justification – and it
justifies nothing
‘5 + (4 + 3) = 5 + (4 + (2 + 1)) = 5+ ((4 + 2) + 1)
=
= (5 + (4 + 2)) = 1 = (5 + (4 + ( 1 + 1))) + 1 =
= (5 + ((4 + 1) + 1)) + 1 = ((5 + (4 +1)) = 1) + 1
=
= (((5 +4) + 1) + 1) + 1 = ((5 + 4) + 2) + 1 = (5 +
4) +3) …(L)
That is a proof of 5 + (4 + 3) = (5 + 4) + 3, but
we can also let it count, i.e. use it, as a proof of 5(+ (4 +4) = (5 + 4) + 4,
etc.
If I say that L is the proof of the propositions a
+ (b + c) = (a + b) = c, the oddness of the step from the proof to the
proposition becomes much more obvious.’
if you know the relevant rules to this sign-game ‘5
+ (4 + 3) = (5 + 4) + 3’ – that is all that counts
and if you know the relevant rules to the sign-game
‘5(+ (4 +4) = (5 + 4) + 4, etc. – that is all that counts
two games – two sets of rules
there is in fact – no question of a so called
‘proof’ – being in any sense relevant here
the question – just does not arise
yes – you can play other sign games that reflect
the relevant rules here –
however doing so adds nothing to the ‘5 + (4 + 3) = (5 + 4) + 3’ game and its rules
proofs are affirmation games – that are entirely
unnecessary – if you know the rules of the game
they don’t in fact serve any logical or
mathematical end
perhaps they serve some psychological need?
or as I like to think they are just fun to do
in any case the fact remains they are part and
parcel of the practice –
perhaps they are really the advertisement for the
product?
if so we shouldn’t be confusing the advertisement
with the product
this whole issue of proof is a good example of just
how rhetoric can infiltrate and take hold in logic
this is no great surprise – but is something
philosophers need to be aware of
‘Definitions merely introduce practical
abbreviations; we could get along without them. But is that true of recursive
definitions?’
‘practical abbreviations’ of? –
rules have to have some formulation – and
directions have to be given – stated –
in so far as definitions do this – they have a
place and function
recursive definitions give rules and direction –
however it is almost as if they have an added
dimension of motion –
and so a more operational sense or focus to them
‘Two different things might be called applications
of the rule a + (b + 1) = (a + b) +1:
in one sense 4 + (2 + 1) = (4 + 2) = (4 + 2) + 1 is
an application, in another sense
4 + (2 + 1) = ((4 + 1) + 1) + 1 = (4 + 2) + 1 is.’
yes – and any rule – is open to different
interpretations – different applications –
so just what application a rule is in fact given –
is a matter of the context or circumstance in which it is used
‘The recursive definition is a rule for
constructing replacement rules, or else the general term of a series of
definitions. It is a signpost that shows the same way to all expressions of a
certain form.’
the recursive definition defines the recursive game
and as for ‘a signpost that shows the way to all
expressions of certain form’ – what else could it be?
any
‘definition’ is a ‘signpost that shows the way to all expressions of a certain
form’
‘As we said, we might write the inductive proof
without using letters at all (with no loss of rigour). Then the recursive
definition a + (b + 1) = (a + b) + 1 would have to be written as a series of
definitions. As things are, this series is concealed in the explanation of its
use. Of course we can keep the letters in the definition for the sake of
convenience, but in that case in the explanation we have to bring in a sign
like
“1, (1) + 1, ((1) + 1) = 1 and so on”, or what
boils down to the same thing,
“| 1, x, x +
1 |”.
But here we mustn’t believe that this sign should really be
“(x). ½1, x, x + 1 |”!’
yes – exactly
‘The point of our formulation is of course that the
concept “all numbers” is given only in a structure like “½1, x, x +
1 |”.
The generality is set out in the
symbolism by this structure and cannot be described by an (x). fx.
Of course the so-called “recursive definition” isn’t
a definition in the customary sense of the word, because it isn’t an equation,
since the equation a + (b + 1) = (a + b)
+1 is only a part of it. Nor is it a logical product of equations.
Instead it is only a law for the construction of equations; just as ½1, x, x +
1 |
isn’t a number but a law etc. (The bewildering thing about the proof of a + (b
+ c) = (a + b) + c is of course that it is supposed to come out of the
definition alone. But µ isn’t a definition, but a
general rule for addition).’
really is it
a law for the construction of
equations? –
isn’t it
rather like this –
that an
equation is given or proposed – and if the ‘recursive definition’ is brought
into play – it sets out an approach to
the equation – effectively – a never ending approach
it is a game
played as were in response to the equation –
the equation
here functions as the limit of the recursive game – a limit that logically
cannot be reached – and so the game goes on – and that’s the idea
‘On the other
hand the generality of this rule is no different from that of the period
division 1 /3 = 0.3. That means, there isn’t anything that the rule
leaves open or in
1
need of completion or the like.’
‘the generality of this rule’ –
generality is non-restrictive – within a given
propositional domain – i.e. the domain of numbers – e.g. ‘all numbers’
a general proposition expresses this
non-restrictiveness
1 /3 = 0.3 – is an equation
– a propositional game – it is a closed propositional system
1
and yes it leaves nothing open –
however it is quite different to “½1, x, x +
1 |”
– to the non-restrictive proposition
the equation is ‘general’ only in the sense that
its domain is non-specific
‘Let us not forget: the sign “|1, x, x +
1|”
… N interests us not as a striking expression for the general term of the
series of cardinal numbers, but only in so far as it is contrasted with signs
of similar construction. N as opposed to
something like
|2,
x, x
+3|;
in short, as a sign, or an instrument, in a calculus. And of course the same
holds for 1 /3 = 0.3. (The only thing left in the rule is its
application.)
1
1 + (1 + 1) = (1 + 1) + 1, 2 + (1 + 1) = (2 + 1) +
1, 3 + (1 + 1) = (3 + 1) + 1 …
and so on
1 + (2 + 1) = (1 + 2) + 1, 2 + (2 +1) = (2 + 2) +
1, 3 + (2 + 1) = (3 + 2) + 1 …
and so on
1 + (3 + 1) = (1 + 3) + 1, 2 + (3 + 1) = (2 + 3) +
1, 3 + (3 + 1) = (3 + 3) + 1 …
and so on
and so on.’
yes – the issue is application / use – in whatever
way the rule is interpreted or signed
‘We might write the rule “a + (b + 1) = (a + b) +
1”, thus.
a +
(1 + 1) = (a + 1) + 1
¯ ¯ R
a +
(x +
1) (a + x)
+ 1
a + ((x +
1) + 1) ((a + x) + ) + 1
In the application of the rule R (and the
description of the application is of course an inherent part of the sign for
the rule), a ranges over the series½1, x, x + 1 |; and of course that might be
expressly stated by an additional sign, say “a ® N”. (We might call the second
and third lines of the R taken together the operation, like the second and
third term of the sign N.) Thus too the explanation of the use of the recursive
definition “a + (b + 1) = (a + b) + 1” is a part of that rule itself; or if you
like a repetition of the rule in another form; just as “1, 1 + 1, 1 + 1 + 1 and
so on” means the same as (i.e. is
translatable into) “|1, x, x +
1|”.
The translation into word-language casts
light on the calculus with new signs, because we have already mastered the
calculus with the signs of word-language.
The sign of the rule, like any other sign, is a
sign belonging to a calculus; its job isn’t
to hypnotize people into accepting an application,
but to be used in the calculus in accordance with a system. Hence the exterior
form is no more essential than that of an arrow ®; what is essential is the system
in which the sign for the rule is employed.
The system of contraries – so to speak – from which
the sign is distinguished etc.
What I am here calling the description of the
application is itself of course something that contains an “and so on”, and so it
can itself be no more a supplement to or substitute for the rule-sign.’
yes the sign of the rule is a sign belonging to a
calculus – a propositional system – a proposition tradition – a propositional
practise
and in the event of different perspectives –
different arguments – and in the development of different traditions –
different signs will be used and developed with different descriptions –
and different practises will come into play
‘and so on’ can well be seen as a supplement or
substitute for the sign rule –
this is neither here nor there
what the game is played with – and how it is
described at a theoretical level – is open to question – open to interpretation
–
however when we get to doing mathematics – actually
playing the game – at the least we begin with the propositional structures that
are already in place
and yes – whether one set of symbols (and all that
goes with it) – has some kind of advantage over another (i.e. simplicity –
clarity – comprehensiveness etc.) – will always be an interesting and useful
question
language is relevant – but action is the game –
and we should at any point in the propositional
action understand that the ground of our symbolism is uncertainty
‘What is the contradictory of a general proposition
like a + (b + (1 + 1)) = a + ((b + 1) + 1)? What is the system of propositions
within which this proposition is negated? Or again, how, and in what form, can
this proposition come into contradiction with others? What question does it
answer? Certainly not the question whether (n).fn or
($n).
~ fn is the
case, because it is the rule R that contributes to the generality of the
proposition. The generality of a rule is eo
ipso incapable of being brought into question.’
the negation of the generality of a rule – has the
effect of just denying the rule –
and prime
facie to do so is an operational dead end
it is not that the generality of the rule is eo ipso incapable of being brought into question – of course it can be brought into question –
it is of the nature of the proposition that it is
open to question – open to doubt –
that it is uncertain
it is just that if it is brought into question –
the game as it is – as it is practised –
will not proceed
and presumably – if it is denied or seriously
questioned – any such denial or doubt would come out of an alternative point of
view which proposes a better way to proceed –
and if it doesn’t come out of a positive
alternative – then it will not be given any
consideration at all
‘Now imagine the general rule written as a series
P11, P12 P13 …
P21 P22 P23 …
P31 P32 P33 …
……………….
and then negated. If we regard it as (x).fx, the we
are treating it as logical product and its opposite is the logical sums of the
denials of p11 ××
p21 × p22 ××× pmn
×
Certainly if you compare the proposition with a logical product, it becomes infinitely
significant and its opposite void of significance). (But remember that the “and
so on” in the proposition comes after a comma, not after an “and” (“ . ”) The
“and so on” is not a sign of incompleteness.)
Is the rule R infinitely significant? Like an
enormously long logical product?
That one can run the number series through the rule
is a form that is given; nothing is affirmed about it and nothing can be denied
about it.
Running the stream of numbers through is not
something which I can prove. I can only prove something about the form, or
pattern, through which I run the numbers.
But we can’t say that the general number rule a +
(b + c) = (a + b) + c …A) has the same generality as a + ( 1 + 1) = a + (a + 1)
+ 1 (in that the latter holds for every cardinal number and the former for
every triple of cardinal numbers) and that the inductive proof of A justifies the rule A? Can we say that we
can give the rule A, since the proof shows that it is always right? Does 1
/3 = 0.3 justify the rule
1
1 2 3
1/3 = 0.3, 1/3 = 0.33, 1/3 = 0.333 and so on” … P)
A is a completely intelligible rule; just like the
replacement rule P. But I can’t give such a rule, for the reason that I can’t
calculate the instances of A by another rule; just as I cannot give P as a rule
if I have given a rule whereby I can calculate
1
1/3 = 0.3 etc.’
the ‘and so on’ – is not a sign of incompleteness –
it is a sign of ‘on-goingness’
‘is the rule R infinitely significant?’
the rule R is a game sign – its action is
on-goingness with no logical end point –
that is the game
‘like an enormous logical product’ –
R is not a logical product – though indeed – R is productive –
a way of looking at is to say –
R is a propositional game – the point of which just
is that it has no logical product
‘That one can run the number series through the
rule is a form that is given; nothing is affirmed about it and nothing can be
denied about it.’
and –
‘Running the stream of numbers through is not
something which I can prove. I can only prove something about the form, or
pattern, through which I run the numbers.’
yes – what we have here is a game
the inductive proof of A – is no more than an
account – an ‘explanation’ of A – effectively – a restatement of it
‘justification’ – if it comes to anything – just
comes down to – use
it is not a question of whether the rule A is
always right – it is rather does it have a function – does it have a use?
and it does not follow that because you can’t
calculate the instances of A by another rule – that you can’t give the (‘completely intelligible’)
rule A
the question is where and how is it to be used
‘But I can’t give such a rule, for the reason that
I can’t calculate the instances of A by another rule; just as I cannot give P
as a rule if I have given a rule whereby I can calculate
1
1/3 = 0.3 etc.’
well that you can’t calculate the instances of A by
another rule – is only to say that the
instances of A will be calculated in terms of a rule and by a method
appropriate to A
in any sophisticated mathematical environment there
will be operative – different paradigms – different propositional systems –
different rules and different methods of calculation –
in such a context we can have parallel and indeed
conflicting propositional games – and of course argument regarding their value
and utility
‘How would it be if someone wanted to lay down “25
x 25 = 625” as a rule in addition to the multiplication rules. (I don’t say “25
x 25 = 624”!) – 25 x 25 = 625 only makes sense if the kind of calculation to
which the equation belongs is already known, and it only makes sense in
connection with that calculation. A only makes sense in connection with A’s own
kind of calculation. For the first question here would be: is that a
stipulation, or a derived proposition? If 25 x 25 = 625 is a stipulation, then
the multiplication sign does not mean the same as it does, e.g. in reality
(that is we are dealing with a different kind of calculation). And if A is a
stipulation, it doesn’t define addition in the same way as if it is a derived
proposition. For in that case the stipulation is of course a definition of the
addition sign, and the rules of the calculation that allow A to be worked out
are a different definition of the same sign. Here I mustn’t forget that µ, b, g isn’t the
proof of A, but only the form of the proof, or what is proved; so µ, b g is a
definition of A.
Hence I can
only say “25 x 25 = 625 is proved” if the method of proof is fixed
independently of the specific proof. For it is this method that settles the
meaning of
“x x
h”
and so settles what is proved. So to
that extent the form a.b = c belongs to the
a
method of proof that defines the sense of the
proposition A.
Arithmetic is complete without a rule like A;
without it it doesn’t lack anything. The proposition A is introduced into
arithmetic with the discovery of periodicity, with the construction of a new calculus. Before this discovery or
construction a question about the correctness of that proposition would have as
little sense as a question about the correctness of “1/3 = 0.3, 1/3 = o.33 … ad
inf.”
The stipulation of P is not the same thing as the
proposition “1/3 = 0.3” and in that
. .
sense “a + (b + c) = (a + b) = c) is different from
the rule (stipulation) such as A. The two belong to different calculi. The
proof of µ, b, g is proof or justification of a rule like A
only in so far as it is the general form of the proof of arithmetical
propositions of the form A.’
laying down a rule – in addition to an arithmetical
rule is either irrelevant – or a
restatement i.e. an abbreviation of the rule –
but Wittgenstein is correct ‘A only makes sense in
connection with A’s own kind of
calculation –
or more generally you can say – calculation is
paradigm dependent – game dependent
so yes –
‘If 25 x 25 – 625 is a stipulation, then the
multiplication sign does not mean the same as it does, e.g. in reality (that is
we are dealing with a different kind of calculation’
‘reality’ by the way is no more than an ‘accepted
or dominant practice’
a stipulation – or – a calculation?
different forms – different approaches – different
practices –
and any form or practice will have its argument –
and its reasons –
what we have to understand is that there are different
ways of proceeding – different methods – different practices – i.e. –
‘The stipulation of P is not the same thing as the
proposition “1/3 = 0.3” and in that
sense “a + (b + c) = (a + b) = c) is different from
the rule (stipulation) such as A. The two belong to different calculi’
and underlying this – is the logical reality – that
any proposal – any proposition – any propositional system – is open –
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
understanding what fits where – what works with what
– is finally a matter of observation –
precise observation – of practice
proof as I have said is restatement – is rhetoric –
however in so far as this notion of proof – is
standard practice – then Wittgenstein’s point that ‘Hence I can only say “25 x 25 = 625 is
proved” if the method of proof is fixed independently of the specific proof’ –
makes sense –
and yes – ‘The
proof of µ, b, g is proof or justification of a rule like A
only in so far as it is the general form of the proof of arithmetical propositions
of the form A.’
this is all
to do with the ritual of proof
the fact of
it is though – arithmetic does not need a ‘rule’ like A –
and
Wittgenstein is right – periodicity is the creation / construction of a new
calculus
a new
numerical game
the relation
of periodicity to arithmetic – is to be described in terms of a family
resemblance between numerical games
and if you
were to go down that path –
you might say
that periodicity launches from an arithmetical background – but once up and
running is quite a different beast
‘Periodicity
is not a sign (symptom) of a decimal’s recurring; the expression “it goes on
like that forever” is only the translation of the sign for periodicity into
another form of expression. (If there was something other than the periodic
sign of which periodicity was only a symptom, that something would have to be a
specific expression, which could be nothing less than the complete expression
of that something.)’
periodicity
– is
the periodic sign – in whatever way it is formulated
the periodic
sign is a game-sign
‘it goes on forever’ – is a characterization of the logic of the recurrence-game – which is
to say a characterization of the proposed action
of the game
37 Seeing or
viewing a sign in a particular manner. Discovering an aspect of a mathematical
expression. “Seeing an expression in a particular way”. Marks of emphasis.
‘Earlier I spoke of the use of connection lines,
underlining etc. to bring out the corresponding, homologous, parts of the
equations of a recursive proof. In the proof

the one marked for µ for example
corresponds not to b but to c in the next
equation; and b corresponds not to d but to e; and g not to d but to c + d, etc.
Or in

i
doesn’t correspond to x and e doesn’t correspond to l; it is b that i corresponds to; and b not
correspond to x, but x corresponds to q and µ to d and b to g and g to m, not to q, and so on
What about a calculation like
(5 + 3)2 = (5 + 3).(5 + 3) = 5. (5 + 3) + 3.(5 + 3) =
= 5.5 + 5.3 + 3.5 + 3.3 = 52 +
2.5.3 + 32 …R)
from which we
can also read a general rule for the squaring of a binomial?
We can as we were look at this calculation
arithmetically or algebraically.’
connection lines are proposals – relational
conjectures –
and behind any such relational conjecture –
argument
‘We can as it were look at this calculation
arithmetically or algebraically’
yes – and the more general point that underlies
this statement is that the proposition is open – open to interpretation
that the ground of our reality – of propositional
reality – is openness –
is uncertainty
and the point just is that our practice doesn’t
diminish this openness – this possibility of propositional interpretation and
innovation –
rather it feeds off it and reflects it
‘The difference between the two ways of looking at
it would have been brought out e.g. if the example had been written
µb b
(5 + 2)2 = 52 + 2.2.5 + 22
In the algebraic way of looking at it we would have
to distinguish the 2 in the position marked µ from the 2s
in the position marked b but in the arithmetical
one they would not need to be distinguished. We are – I believe – using a
different calculus in each case.’
yes – a
different calculus in each case –
algebra and
arithmetic – are related but different games –
that is different
propositional constructs
so how you
play them will be different
‘how you
play’ – is the calculus
‘According to
one and not the other way of looking at it the calculation above, for instance,
would be a proof of (7 + 8)2 = 82 = 2 .7. 8 + 82.’
yes – you
could play this propositional game
bare in mind
– proof is a restatement –
and if you
are operating within one propositional form – a restatement of a proposition in
that form – should be possible –
and some
restatements are quite ingenious
‘We might
work out an example to make sure that (a + b)2 is equal to a2 + b2 +
2ab, not a2 + b2 +
3ab – if we had forgotten it for instance; but we couldn’t check in that sense
whether the formula holds generally.
But of course there is that
sort of check too, in the calculation
(5 + 3)2
= … = 52 + 2.5.3 + 32
I might check
whether the 2 in the second summand is a general feature of the equation or
something that depends on the particular numbers occurring in the example.’
checking here
is what?
proposal –
and argument
the
calculation is of course open – open to question – open to interpretation –
as is any
proposal or argument in relation to it
‘I turn (5 +
2)2 = 52 + 2.2.5
into another sign, if I write
µ b µ- - bµ b-
(5 + 2)2
= 52 + 2.2.5 + 22
and thus
“indicate which features of the right hand side originate from the particular
numbers on the left” etc.
(Now I
realize the importance of this process of coordination. It expresses a new way
of looking at the calculation and therefore a way of looking at a new
calculation.)’
yes – any
proposition – any proposal – is open
-
open to
propositional interpretation – open to propositional invention –
in
mathematics we work with propositional structures –
the essential
characteristic of these structure is uncertainty –
this the
ground of creativity
‘ ‘In order
to prove A’ – we could say – I first of all have to draw attention to quite
definite features of B. (As in the division 1.0/3 = 0.
).’

this is just
to say that ‘drawing attention’ – is proposing
–
and the only
restrictions on this are those you impose yourself –
for whatever
reason
‘(And µ had no suspicion, so to speak, of what I see
if I do.)
Here the relationship
between generality is like the relationship between existence and the proof of
existence.’
the ‘proof’
of existence – is the assertion – of
…
‘When µ, b g are proved,
the general calculus has still to be discovered.’
when µ, b g are proposed
and argued for –
the general
calculus has still to be proposed –
argued for –
and accepted
(used)
‘Writing “ a
+ (b + c) = (a + b) + c” in the induction series seems to us a matter of
course, because we don’t see that by doing so we are starting a totally new
calculus. (A child just learning to do sums would see clearer than we do in
this connection.)’
yes –
or it just
puts pay to the induction as such
that there is
this proposition in the inductive series – compromises the induction –
this doesn’t
mean that the series with the proposition will not be used –
if it is –
its description in logical terms becomes obviously questionable –
a moment of
truth
‘Certain
features are brought out by the schema R; they could be specifically marked
thus:

Of course it
would also have been enough (i.e. it would have been a symbol of the same
multiplicity) if we had B and added
f1 x = a + (b + x), f2 x = (a + b) + x
(Here we must
also remember that every symbol – however explicit – can be misunderstood.)’
the point is
rather that regardless of how explicit a symbol is – it is open to interpretation
and what of
‘explicit’? –
apart from
the fact that the symbol is made and is apparent – written –
‘explicit’
only has any meaning – sharp or not – in terms of the interpretation given it
‘The first
person to draw attention to the fact that B can be seen in that way introduces
a new sign whether or not he goes on to attach special marks to B or to write
the schema R beside it. In the latter case R itself is the new sign, or if you
prefer, B plus R. It is the way in which he draws attention to it that produces
the new sign.’
that ‘B can
be seen in that way’ –
if a new way
of seeing is proposed – then the new proposal needs to be distinguished from
the previous understanding if it is to be ‘real’ – functional and useful – it
(the new proposal ) – must be signed – in some way or another – otherwise for
all intents
and purposes
– it doesn’t exist – it’s not there
how he draws
attention to it – will most likely be an
account of how he came up with the new sign –
but really
this ‘how’– in terms of the signs utility –
is neither
here nor there
‘We might
perhaps say that here the lower equation is used as a + b = b + a; or similarly
that here B is used as A, by being as it were read sideways. Or: B was used as
A, but the new proposition was built up from µ. b . g, in such a way that though
A is now read out of B, µ. b . g don’t appear in the sort of abbreviation in
which the premises turn up in the conclusion.’
in some ways
this is just like looking at a picture – i.e. a picture in a gallery
in this case
a straightforward propositional picture –
but in
logical terms – it is no more than to say that any proposal – any proposition –
indeed – any propositional construct – is
open to question – open to
interpretation –
this is
always on the go – in any propositional context –
a particular
interpretation is adopted by a particular group – at a particular time – for a
particular purpose
‘What does it
mean to say: ”I am drawing your attention to the fact that the same sign occurs
here in both function signs (perhaps you didn’t notice)”? Does that mean that
he didn’t understand the proposition? – After all, what he didn’t notice was
something which belonged essentially to the proposition; it wasn’t as if it was
some external property of the proposition he hadn’t noticed (Here again we see
what kind of thing is called “understanding a proposition”.)’
what does it
mean?
well frankly
it could mean anything –
it could be a
statement of the obvious –
it could be a
direction of focus that the other had not had –
it could be a
lead into an argument –
who is to
say?
the point is
unless you are in that particular context – at that particular time you don’t
really have a start here
of course we
can speculate – but that as it turns out is all we can do –
even in a
particular context at a particular time
‘understanding
a proposition’ –
just is
recognizing that any proposition – that is – any proposal – is open to question
– open to doubt – is – logically speaking – uncertain
drawing
attention – is proposing –
it is simply
– common and garden –
propositional
activity
‘Of course
the picture of reading a sign lengthways and sideways is once again a logical picture, and for that reason it
is a perfectly exact expression of a grammatical relation. We mustn’t say of it
“it’s a mere metaphor, who knows what the facts are really like?”’
yes we begin
with a logical picture – but the truth is that any picture – any picture at all
– is a logical picture –
‘logical’ –
in that a ‘picture’ – any picture – is open to question – open to interpretation
in the
absence of interpretation what you have is an unknown –
our
‘knowledge’ is our proposals – our responses to the unknown – our
interpretations
reading a
picture lengthways – is a different
interpretation to reading it sideways
any expression
of a grammatical relation – that is any proposal of a grammatical relation – is
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
exactness is
a rhetorical ploy
‘who knows
what the facts are really like?’ –
the facts –
are just what is proposed
‘When I said
that the new sign with the marks of emphasis must have been derived from the
old one without the marks, that was meaningless, because of course I can
consider the sign with the marks without regard to its origin. In that case it
presents itself to me as three equations (Frege), that is as the shape of three
equations with certain underlings, etc.
It is
certainly significant that this shape is quite similar to the three equations
without the under linings; it is also significant that the cardinal number 1
and the rational number 1 are governed by similar rules; but that does not
prevent what we have here from being a new sign. What I am now doing with this
sign is something quite new.’
yes
‘Isn’t this
like the supposition I once made that people might have operated the
Frege-Russell calculus of truth functions with the signs “~” and “.” combined
into
“~p. ~q”
without anyone noticing, and that Sheffer, instead of giving a new definition,
had merely drawn attention to a property of signs already in use.’
We might have gone on dividing without ever
becoming aware of recurring decimals. When we have seen them, we have seen
something new.’
we are not
dealing here with the properties of signs –
or to put it
bluntly signs as such have no properties –
signs are
tools of use –
the question
is only – how are they used? –
and yes you
can background use with theory – i.e. talk of ‘properties’ –
and doing so
you may well bolster (rhetorically) an argument for use –
but one has
to be careful here about putting the cart before the horse
Sheffer – in
‘drawing attention to a property of signs already in use’ –
was actually proposing a new and different use
and yes –
unless something new is proposed –
you will operate with the proposals in play – that is you will operate with the
status quo
‘But couldn’t
we extend that and say “I might have multiplied numbers together without ever
noticing the special case in which I multiply a number by itself; and that
means ‘x2’ the expression of our having become aware of that special
case. Or, we might have gone on multiplying a by b and dividing it by c without
noticing that we could write “a.b” as “a.(b.c)” or that the latter is
similar to a.b. Or again, this is like a
c
savage who
doesn’t yet see the analogy between ½½½½½
and ½½½½½½,
or between
½½and
½½½½½.’
yes – what
you are aware of – and what you might notice – depends in the first place on
the propositional context or contexts that you can bring to bear –
in short
the state of knowledge you have access to
which means
– what has been proposed – and what – of what has been proposed – has a
currency – as determined by yourself and the others who have a stake in the
matter under consideration
as for the
savage – the savage sees what he sees – and proposes what he proposes –
just like
the mathematician

‘You might
see the definition U, without knowing why I use that abbreviation.
You might see
the definition without understanding its point. – But its point is something new,
not something already contained in it as a specific replacement rule.’
any use of
any proposal – definition or not – is open to question – to doubt – is
uncertain – at any stage of its use
not knowing
‘why’ someone uses a proposition / definition – or understanding its point –
opens its use up to question and invites explanation
and if a
definition / proposition – is ‘new’ – what we will look for is a demonstration
of its utility
‘Of course, “Á” isn’t an equals-sign in the same sense as
the ones occurring in µ, b, g.
But we can
easily show that that “Á” has certain formal properties in common
with =.’
the use of a
sign – and an unusual sign in a particular context – begs explanation –
that is to
say if we were to proceed with such a sign we would be looking for
propositional elaboration
‘It would be
incorrect – according to the postulated rules – to use the equals-sign like
this:
D …½(a
+ b)2 = a.(a + b) + b.(a + b)
= … =
= a2 + 2ab + b2½.
= .½(a
+ b)2 = a2 + 2ab +
b2 ½
if that is supposed to mean that the left hand side
is the proof of the right.
But mightn’t we imagine this equation regarded as a
definition? For instance, if it had always been the custom to write out the
whole chain instead of the right hand side, and we introduced the whole
abbreviation.’
‘postulated rules’ – the rules in use –
and yes we can imagine
– or re-imagine the ‘equation’ – the string of symbols –
in the end how the symbolism is used – is a matter
of practice – that is to say – just how it is
used –
if the symbolism is re-imagined in away that
practitioners don’t understand – that is to say in a way that is not considered
functional in the current propositional / mathematical environment –
then the new interpretation will not be used –
it will not get a guernsey
‘Of course D can be regarded as a definition! Because
the sign on the left hand side is in fact used, and there is no reason why we
shouldn’t abbreviate it according to the convention. Only in that case either
the sign on the right or the sign on the left is used in a different way from
the one now usual.
It can never
be sufficiently emphasized that totally
different kinds of sign-rules get written in the form of an equation.
The ‘definition’ x.x = x2 might be
regarded as merely allowing us to replace the sign “x.x” by the sign x2,”
like the definition “1+ 1 = 2”; but it can also be regarded (and in fact is
regarded) as allowing us to put a2 instead of a.a, and (a + b)2
instead of
(a + b).(a + b) and in such a way that any
arbitrary number can be substituted for the x.
A person who discovers that a proposition p follows
from one of the form q É p.q constructs a new sign, the
sign for that rule. (I am assuming that a calculus with
p, q, É, has already been in use, and that
this rule is now added to make it a new calculus.)’
yes
‘It is true that the notation “x2” takes
away the possibility of replacing one of the factors x by another number.
Indeed, we could imagine two stages in the discovery (or construction) of x2..
At first, people might have written “x=” instead of “x2”,
before it occurred to them that there was a system x.x, x.x.x, etc; later they
might have hit upon that too. Similar things have occurred in mathematics
countless times. (In Leibig’s sign for an oxide oxygen did not appear as an
element in the same way as what was oxidized. Odd as it sounds, we might even
today, with all the data available to us, give oxygen a similarly privileged
position – only in the form of
representation – by adopting an incredibly artificial interpretation, i.e.
grammatical construction.)’
yes – one way or another it is a question of
construction – propositional construction –
and indeed any proposition – any construction – is
open to question – open to doubt –
the question is what will work in what
propositional context?
‘The definitions x.x = x2, x.x.x = x3
don’t bring anything into the world except the signs “x2” and “x3”
(and thus so far it isn’t necessary to write numbers as exponents).’
it may not be ‘necessary’ – but it is a practise –
an accepted practise – and I would say – obviously useful
‘½The
process of generalization creates a new sign-system½’
ok – if that’s how it goes
‘Of course Scheffer’s discovery is not the
discovery of the definition ~p. ~q = p½q.
Russell might well have given that definition without being in possession of
Scheffer’s system, and on the other hand Scheffer might have built up his
system without the definition. His system is contained in the use of the signs
“~p.
~q” for
“~p”
and “~(~p.
~q). ~(~p.
~q)” for “p v q” and all “p½q”
does is to permit an abbreviation. Indeed, we can say that
someone could well have been acquainted with the use of the sign “~(~p.
~q). ~(~p.
~q)” for “p v q” without recognizing the system
p½q.
½. p½q.
in it.’
yes – an abbreviation
here we are talking about interpretation of symbolic proposals
– symbolic propositions
and look an interpretation – variation –
abbreviation – is valid if it functions –
and whether it functions or not is a matter of
argument
the fact is logicians and mathematicians come at
propositional representation from different points of view – different
propositional paradigms –
so at the least – in any vibrant intellectual
context – you might expect different formulations
and that a formal proposition can be written in a
different manner just points to the underlying uncertainty of any propositional
construction or use
a proposition – whatever form it takes – is a
proposal – open to question – open to doubt – thus – uncertain
and this is to state the obvious –
logic and mathematics are explorations of
uncertainty
‘It makes it clearer if we adopt Frege’s two
primitive signs “~”
and “.”. The discovery isn’t lost if the definitions are written ~p. ~p = ~p and ~(~p. ~p).
~(~q. ~q) = p.q. Here apparently nothing at all has been altered in the
original signs.’
yes
and
‘primitive’ – is just the decision to suspend question – suspend doubt –
to make a
play for certainty
‘primitive’ –
is rhetoric
‘But we might also imagine someone’s having written
the whole Fregian or Russellian logic in this system, and yet, like Frege,
calling, “~”
and “.”. his primitive signs, because he
did not see the other system in his propositions.’
yes – of course
‘It is clear that the discovery of Sheffer’s system
in ~. p. ~p = ~p
and ~(~p. ~p). ~(q. ~q) = p. q corresponds to the discovery that x2 + ax + a2
is a specific instance of
4
a2
+ 2ab + b2.’
a fair enough argument
‘We don’t see that something can be looked at in a
certain way until it is so looked at.
We don’t see that an aspect is possible until it is
there.’
we don’t see what is there until it is proposed
‘That sounds as if Sheffer’s discovery wasn’t
capable of being represented in signs at all. (Periodic division). But that is
because we can’t smuggle the use of the sign into its introduction (the rule is
and remains a sign, separated from its application).’
Sheffer put up a proposal – and in so doing –
represented it in signs
yes – the rule is and remains conceptually
separated from its application –
without the separation – no rule or application –
no game
‘Of course I can only apply the general rule for
the induction proof when I discover the substitution that makes it applicable.
So it would be possible for someone to see the equations
(a + 1) + 1 = (a + 1) + 1
1 + (a + 1) = (1 + a) + 1
without hitting on the substitution

first and foremost the equations are proposals – are propositions –
how they are interpreted – what paradigms they are
used in – what overriding propositional constructions they are placed in – is
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
the substitution here is a representation of an
interpretation – of a use
‘Moreover if I say that I understand the equations
as particular cases of the rule, my understanding has to be the understanding
that shows itself in the explanations of the relation between the rule and the
equations, i.e. what we express by the substitutions. If I don’t regard that as
an expression of what I understand, then nothing is an expression of it; but in
that case it makes no sense either to speak of understanding or to say that I
understand something definite. For it only makes sense to speak of understanding
in cases where we understand one thing as opposed to another. And it is this
contrast that signs express.’
‘Moreover if I say that I understand the equations
as particular cases of the rule, my understanding has to be the understanding
that shows itself in the explanations of the relation between the rule and the
equations, i.e. what we express by the substitutions.’
the equations express the rule –
the rule determines the propositional action of the
equations
the equations reflect the rule
the rule is reflected in the equations –
if the rule is not consistent with the equation –
or the equations are not consistent with the rule –
there is no functional relation –
no relation
any functional relation is first and foremost a proposal –
open to question – open to doubt – uncertain –
in short – a subject for argument
substitutions are proposals of equivalence
‘For it only makes sense to speak of understanding
in cases where we understand one thing as opposed to another. And it is this
contrast that signs express.’
a sign is a proposal
different
proposals express different understandings
understanding any proposal – any proposition –
logically speaking is never complete
and our proposals can be understood in a variety of
ways
at different times – our understandings are
different
‘Indeed, seeing the internal relation must in its
turn be seeing that it can be described, something of which one can say: “I see
that such and such is the case”; it has to be really something of the same kind
as the correlation-signs (like connecting lines, brackets, substitutions, etc).
Everything else has to be contained in the application of the sign of the
general rule in a particular case.’
‘I see that such and such is the case’ – is accepting the proposal – it is
affirmation of the proposal in play
and yes this acceptance will most likely be
facilitated – if the ‘internal relation’ is expressed in terms that have
‘something of the same kind of correlation-signs’
‘everything else has to be contained in the
application of the sign of the general rule in a particular case.’
well this is the idea – and the idea determines or
guides the practice
still it must be remembered that whether in fact it
is the case that ‘everything else is contained in the application of the sign
of the general rule in a particular case’ – is a matter always open to question
–
‘It is as if we had a number of material objects
and discovered they had surfaces which enabled them to be placed in a
continuous row. Or rather, as if we discovered that such and such surfaces,
which we had seen before, enabled them to be placed in a continuous row. That
is the way many games and puzzles are solved.’
yes – different applications – different uses –
different games
‘The person who discovers periodicity invents a new
calculus. The question is, how does the calculus with the periodic division
differ from the calculus in which periodicity is unknown?’
look – and you will see
‘(We might have operated a calculus with cubes
without having had the idea of putting them together to make prisms.)’
yes –
but you if have the idea of putting the cubes
together to make a prism –
your idea will be a calculation
Appendix1
1. Remarks taken from the
Manuscript volume. Wittgenstein omitted them. Even in the MS they are not set
out together as they are here.
(On: The process of generalization creates a new
sign-system)
‘It is a very important observation that the c in A
is not the same variable as the c in
b and g. So the way I wrote out the proof was not
quite correct in a respect which is very important for us. In A we could
substitute n for c, whereas the cs in b and g are identical.
But another
question arises: can I derive from A that i + (k + c) = (i + k) + c? If so why
can’t I derive it in the same way from B? Does that mean that a and b
in A are not identical with a and b in µ, b and g?
We see
clearly that that the variable c in B isn’t identical with c in A if we put a
number instead of it. Then B is something like
µ 4 + (5 + 1) = (4 + 5) + 1
b 4 + (5 + (6 + 1)) = (4 + (5 + 6)) + 1 }
… W
g (4 + 5) + (6 + 1) = ((4 + 5) + 6) + 1
but that
doesn’t have corresponding to it an equation like Aw:
4 + (5 + 6) =
(4 + 5) + 6!
What makes
the induction proof different from a proof of A is expressed in the fact that c in B is not identical with the one in
A, so that we could use different letters in two places.
All that is
meant by what I have written above is that the reason it looks like an
algebraic proof of A is that we think we meet the same variables a, b, c in the
equation A as in µ, b g and so we regard A as a result of a
transformation of these equations.
(Whereas of
course in reality I regard the signs µ, b g, in quite a different way, which means that
c in b and g isn’t used as a variable in the same way as
a and b. Hence one can express this new view of B, by saying that c does not
occur in A)
What I said
about the new way of regarding µ, b g might be put like this: µ is used to build up b and g in exactly the same way as
the fundamental algebraic equations are used to build up an equation like (a +
b)2 = a2 + 2ab + b2. But if that is the way
they are derived, we are regarding the complex µ, b g in a new way when we give
the variable c a function which differs from that of a and b (c becomes a hole
through which the stream of numbers has to flow).’
so the proof
of A is different to the proof of B –
the two
arguments are not identical –
that I would
have thought is obvious
what we have
is different mathematical perspectives – different proofs – different propositional games
that they can
be seen to be related – is no big news –
and yes –
different letters in two places – might have saved – time –
and might
have avoided a rather unnecessary discussion
38. Proof by
induction, arithmetic and algebra
‘Why do we need the
commutative law? Not so as to be able to write the equation
4 + 6 = 6 + 4, because that
equation is justified by its own particular proof. Certainly the proof of the
commutative law can certainly be used to prove it, but in that case it becomes
just a particular arithmetical proof. So the reason that I need the law is to
apply it when using letters.
And it is this
justification that the inductive proof cannot give me.
However, one thing is clear:
if the recursive proof gives us the right to calculate algebraically, then so
does the arithmetical proof L.
Again: the recursive proof
is – of course – essentially concerned with numbers. But what use are numbers
to me when I want to operate purely algebraically? Or again, the recursion
proof is only of use to me when I want to use it to justify a step in a number
calculation.’
the
‘commutative law’ – is a sign game – a substitution game
and yes we
play this came with letters
why do we
need the commutative law?
it has its
uses
a game is played
– there is no question of justifying a game – you play it – or you don’t
as to
induction –
induction
is a form of suggestive proposal – it is not a game
a so called
‘inductive proof’ is no more than an exercise in speculation
it is a
proposal – open to question – open to doubt – uncertain –
it justifies
nothing
and in any
case justification is rhetoric – or if stripped of pretension –
it is the
decision to stop – to stop questioning – and to proceed
yes – the
recursive game – facilitates algebraic calculation
as does the
arithmetical game L (see page 428)
‘But what
use are numbers to me when I want to operate purely algebraically?’
of no use
‘Or Again,
the recursion proof is only of use to me
when I want to justify a step in a number calculation.’
in so far
as there is no ‘justification’ in a number game –
the
recursion game – will be of no use to you
‘But someone might ask: do
we need both the inductive proof and the associative law, since the latter
cannot provide a foundation for calculation with numbers, and the former cannot
provide one for the transformations in algebra?’
if they have a use – they
have a use
‘Well, before Skolem’s
proof was the associative law, for example, just accepted without anyone’s
being able to work out the corresponding step in a numerical calculation? That
is, were we previously unable to work out 5 + (4 +3) = (5 + 4) + 3, and did we
treat it as an axiom?’
strictly speaking – if you understand the game – the
equation-game – there is nothing as such to work out
Skolem’s proof – when it comes down to it is no
more than a restatement of the
equation –
and that is all a ‘working out’ will ever be –
restatement
we are dealing here with a propositional game
you play
the game – and you play according to the rule –
there is no deeper explanation –
and yes restating the game – even reconfiguring it
– can be all part of playing it –
‘If I say that the periodic calculation proves the
proposition that justifies me in those steps, what would the proposition have
been like if it had been assumed as an axiom instead of being proved?’
it would be no different –
how you account for / ‘prove’ the game – is not the game –
any proof is simply an argument – open to question
– open to doubt – uncertain –
of interest – yes – but it’s not the game – not playing the game
‘What would a proposition be like that permitted
one to put 5 + (7 + 9) = (5 + 7) + 9) without being able to prove it? Is it
obvious that there never has been such a proposition.’
well – Wittgenstein has proposed such a proposition
here –
presumably to demonstrate that it is not consistent
with relevant rules – that it has no utility
‘But couldn’t we also say that associative law
isn’t used at all in arithmetic and that we work only with particular number
calculations?’
yes – you could argue that
‘Even when algebra uses arithmetic, it is a totally
different calculus, and cannot be derived from the arithmetical one.’
a different game – yes
‘To the question “is 5 x 4 = 20”? one might answer:
“let’s check whether it is an accord with the basic rules of arithmetic” and
similarly I might say: let’s check whether A is in accord with the basic rules.
But with which rules? Presumably with µ.’
different constructions –
different games – different rules –
and if the question arises
– which rules apply? –
the matter will be open to
discussion – open to question
‘But before we can bring µ and A together we need to stipulate what we
want to call “agreement” here.
That means
that µ and A are separated by the
gulf between arithmetic and algebra,1 and if B is to count as a
proof of A, this gulf has to be bridged over by a stipulation.’
1. to repeat, µ is: a + (b + 1) = (a + b) + 1
A is: a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c.
the gulf between arithmetic
and algebra –
bridged by a ‘stipulation’
– yes – that is bridged by a proposal –
and presumably such a
proposal if it facilitates functionality will be entertained
‘It is clear that we do use
an idea of this kind of agreement when, for instance, we quickly work out a
numerical example to check the correctness of an algebraic proposition.
And in this sense I might
e.g. calculate
25 x 16 16
x 25
25 32
150 80
400 400
and say: “yes, it’s right,
a.b is equal to b.a” – if I imagine that I have forgotten.’
so proposing a restatement
of an algebraic proposal in arithmetical terms – shows what?
that a proposal can be
translated –
the question is does doing
so have any functional value –
or is it just effectively a
word-game – a substitution game?
‘Considered as a rule for algebraic calculation, A
cannot be proved recursively. We would see that especially clearly if we wrote
down the “recursive proof” as a series of arithmetical expressions. Imagine
them written out (i.e. a fragment of the series plus “so on”) without any
intention of “proving” anything, and the suppose someone asks: does that prove
a+(b + c) = (a + b) + c?”. We would ask in astonishment “How can it prove
anything of the kind? The series contains only numbers, it doesn’t contain any
letters”. – But no doubt we might say: if I introduce A as a rule for the
calculation with letters, that brings this calculus in a certain sense into
unison with the calculus of the cardinal numbers, the calculus I established by
the law for the rules of addition (the recursive definition a + (b + 1) = (a +
b) + 1).’
‘Considered as a rule for algebraic calculation, A
cannot be proved recursively’ –
correct
‘if I introduce A as a rule for the calculation
with letters, that brings this calculus in a certain sense into unison with the
calculus of the cardinal numbers’
yes –
what we then have effectively – is a proposal for
the translation of one propositional construct into another – or the use of one
in place of the other –
however the algebraic argument and the recursive argument
are different games
they come out of different logical perspectives –
so any ‘translation proposal’ one way or the other
– strikes me as no more than a word-game – and a superficial one at that –
and in any case it’s really just a hijacking of one propositional construct
by another –
and to what purpose?
I fail to see how this ‘translating’ one into
another –
adds anything to either perspective –
to either game
No comments:
Post a Comment