IV ON CARDINAL NUMBERS
18 Kinds of
cardinal numbers
‘What are numbers? – What numerals signify; an
investigation of what they signify is an investigation of the grammar of
numerals.’
numbers are signs in a sign game – the sign game of
calculation
‘what numerals signify’? –
numerals are a standard representation of numbers –
but what you have to understand is that ‘number’ –
is no more than a term for ‘that which
is counted’ – whatever that is
‘number’ is a standard or formal term for ‘that’ –
and ‘that’ of course in a final sense – is
without definition –
and we don’t concern ourselves with any definition
– proposed definitions – for definitions are irrelevant to the action of
counting – to the counting game
and so – simply because it is convenient and useful
to call ‘that which is counted’ – something –
we give it the name – ‘number’ – knowing full well
– it could be anything – and that it is nothing
nothing but a tag in an action – in a game –
a record of a step in an action – a record of a
play in a game –
‘an investigation of what they (numerals) signify’?
there is nothing to investigate –
unless you are a linguist or an anthropologist – or
a game designer
what do numerals signify?
to the mathematician – it doesn’t matter what they signify
–
the point is their use in the calculation game
what do the draughtsmen in a game of draughts
signify?
‘the grammar of numerals’?
the grammar of numerals – is the use of numerals –
which amounts to the rules that govern that use –
that govern the practice
‘What we are looking for is not a definition of the
concept of number, but an exposition of the grammar of the word “number” and of
the numerals.’
the definition of the concept of number – is whatever description is used to account
for the use of numbers
in mathematics that amounts to an account of the
rules that govern number practice by
mathematicians
‘an exposition of the grammar of the word “number”
and of numerals –
is an account of just how ‘number’ is used – and an
account of just how numerals are used
definition and exposition – description of use –
and any definition – any exposition – will of
course be open to question – open to doubt – uncertain
‘The reason why there are infinitely many cardinal
numbers, is that we construct this infinite system and call it the stem of
cardinal numbers. There is also a number system “1, 2, 3, 4, 5, many” and even
a system “1, 2, 3, 4, 5 ”. Why shouldn’t I call that too a system of cardinal
numbers (a finite one)?’
the reason why there are infinitely many cardinal
numbers –
is simply because the sign operation – the game –
that is cardinality – is repeatable
where a decision is made that an operation is not
repeatable –
the operation is finite – the game is finite
‘It is clear that the axiom of infinity is not what
Russell took it for; it is neither a proposition of logic, nor as it stands a
proposition of physics. Perhaps the calculus to which it belongs, transplanted
into quite different surroundings (with a quite different “interpretation”),
might somewhere find an application; I do not know.
One might say of logical concepts (e.g. of the, or
a, concept of infinity) that their essence proves their existence’
yes – the axiom of infinity might find an application
it is not that the essence of a logical concept
proves its existence
when you strip away all the obfuscation and
pretension (‘essence’) – what you have
is a proposal – and yes – when put it exists
‘(Frege would have said: “perhaps there are people
who have not got beyond the first five in their acquaintance with the series of
cardinal numbers (and see the rest of the series only in an indeterminate form
or something of the kind), but this series exists independently of us”. Does
chess exist independently of us, or not? –)’
all very well to propose that something we
do – or if you like something that we make or create – exists independently
of us – but a tough one to argue
actually it’s just rubbish
‘Here is a very interesting question about the
position of the concept of number in logic: what happens to the concept of
number if a society has no numerals, but for counting, calculating, etc. uses
exclusively an abacus like an Russian abacus?
(Nothing would be more interesting than to
investigate the arithmetic of such people; it would make one really understand
that there is no distinction between 20 and 21.)’
what is relevant is the action of counting –
what you call what you count with – numbers – beads
– colours or whatever – is logically speaking – irrelevant
in different cultures you have different
descriptions – different protocols –
20 and 21 – are steps in the action in a game of counting
–
they are actions
– in the game
actions that have no logical distinction –
except as determined by the rules of the game
‘Could we also imagine, in contrast with the
cardinal numbers, a kind of number consisting of a series like the cardinal
numbers without the 5? Certainly; but this kind of number couldn’t be used for
any of the things for which we use the cardinal numbers. The way in which these
numbers are missing a five is not like the way in which an apple may have been
taken out of a box of apples and can be put back again; it is of their essence
to lack a 5; they do not know the 5
(in the way that the cardinal numbers do not know the number ½.). So these
numbers (if you want to call them that) would be used in cases where the
cardinal numbers (with the 5) couldn’t meaningfully be used.
(Doesn’t the nonsensicality of the talk of the
“basic intuition” show itself here?)’
different ways of calculating – different games
‘basic intuition’ – a piece of rhetoric –
just a way of big-noting – a starting point –
and in any case how you describe where you start –
is irrelevant –
irrelevant to the action of calculating –
to the play of the game – whatever the game
‘When intuitionists speak of the “basic intuition”
– is this a psychological process? If
so, how does it come into mathematics? Isn’t what
they mean only a primitive sign (in Frege’s sense); an element of a calculus?’
it depends on how they define basic intuition –
to my mind it’s a throw back notion – to the idea
of certain knowledge –
a notion which has no place in propositional logic
it doesn’t ‘come into’ mathematics – mathematics
gets on with its business – with or without such epistemological clouds
and as for ‘primitive sign’ – again – just rhetoric
–
a primitive sign – is a sign you stop questioning –
or it’s just simply whatever you decide to work with
there is no sign – no proposal – that is beyond
question – beyond doubt
propositional logic – is the logic of uncertainty
the hard reality is – we propose signs – and we use
them to suit our purposes –
they are a means to an end
and whatever the means – whatever the end –
a question – a doubt – an uncertainty
‘Strange as it sounds, it possible to know the
prime numbers – let’s say – only up to 7 and thus to have a finite system of
prime numbers. And what we call the discovery that there are infinitely many
primes is in truth the discovery of a new system with no greater rights than
the other.’
yes – and it is to say that we can continue to play
the prime-game
‘If you close your eyes and see countless
glimmering spots of light coming and going, as we might say, it doesn’t make
sense to speak of a ‘number’ of simultaneously seen dots. And you can’t say
“there is always a definite number of spots there, we just don’t know what it
is”; that would correspond to a rule where you can speak of checking the
number’
‘there is always a definite number of spots there
we just don’t know what it is’ –
is to say we can’t count here –
and if we can’t count – we can’t say there is a
number
and if we could count we could say
if this is so – the focus then is properly – not on
the symbols (the numbers) used to count– but on the action of counting
if you can’t perform the action – the symbol – that
would be the result of the action – just isn’t there –
there is no
count – there is no number
‘(It makes sense to say: I divide many among many.
But the proposition “I couldn’t divide the many nuts among the many people”
can’t mean that it was logically impossible. Also you can’t say in some cases
it is impossible to divide many among many and in others not”; for in that case
I ask: in which cases is this possible and in which impossible? And to that no
further answer can be given in the many-system.)’
it depends what the relation between the many and
the many is –
if there is a relation of cardinality the division
game can be played – with the result – a whole number
if there is no cardinality – the results can be
either whole numbers – real numbers – or fractions
it depends too – on what result you are looking for
–
if you are only after a whole number result – then
clearly there will be contexts in which the division game will not function
‘To say of a part of my visual field that it has no
colour is nonsense; and of course it is equally nonsense to say that it has
colour (or a colour). On the other hand it makes sense to say it has only one colour
(is monochrome, or uniform in colour) or that it has at least two colours, only
two colours, etc.
So in the sentence “this square in my visual field
has at least two colours” I cannot
substitute “one” for “two”. Or again: “the square has only one colour”
does not mean – on the analogy of ($x).fx. ~ ($x,y). ).fx.
fy
– “the square has one colour but not two colours”.’
colour – or no colour – is really just a question
of description – the use of a description – and whatever that description is
taken to imply –
the visual field – in the absence of description –
as with any other epistemological focus – is an unknown
and any so called ‘natural description’ – is logically speaking no different to what
you might call a non-natural description i.e. a theoretical description –
natural or non-natural – any description is open to
question – open to doubt – is uncertain
what we count is description – not a particular
description – but any description –
and ‘any description’ – in the mathematics game is
given the formal name of ‘number’ –
numerals – colours – beads – whatever – descriptions –
all covered by ‘number’
and to understand ‘number’ you have to understand
the number game
we play a game with description – and that game is
arithmetic
‘one’ is not ‘two’ – therefore ‘one’ cannot be
substituted for ‘two’ –
however the proposition
– ‘this square has at least one colour’ – though a different proposition to –
‘this square in my visual field has at least two colours’ – is consistent with
it –
and yes – the proposition – ‘the square has one
colour but not two colours’ – does not mean the same as – ‘this square has only
one colour’ – but the two propositions are consistent
‘I am speaking here of the case in which it is
senseless to say “that part of space has no colour”. If I am counting the
uniform (monochrome) patches in the square, it does incidentally make sense to
say there aren’t any there at all, if the colour of the square is continually
changing. In that case of course it does make sense to say that there are one
or more uniformly coloured patches in the square and also that the square has
one colour and not two – But for the moment I am disregarding that use of the
sentence “the square has no colour” and am speaking of a system in which it would
be called a matter of course that an area of a surface had a colour, a system,
therefore in which strictly speaking there is no such proposition. If you call
the proposition self-evident you really mean something that is expressed by a
grammatical rule giving the form of a proposition about visual space, for
instance. If you now begin the series of statements giving the number of
colours in the square with the proposition “there is one colour in the square”,
then of course that mustn’t be the proposition of grammar about the
“colouredness” of space.’
the proposition – ‘that part of
space has no colour’ – is not senseless
it points to the fact that the
theory of colour in use has no account of that part of space – or that that the
colour game in play – cannot be played in that part of space
and if you hold that all parts of
space are coloured –
then relative to your theory of
colour – you would regard the statement as false
there is no ‘self-evident
proposition’ –
any proposition – any proposal – is
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
‘self-evidence’ – is illogical –
it is pretentious – and the
notion functions as a rhetorical device –
it’s point is to shut down question and doubt – and pretend –
certainty
‘the proposition of grammar about
the colouredness of space’?
firstly ‘grammar’ – is an account
of usage –
a proposition of grammar about
the colouredness of space
is a theory of the usage of
propositions about the colouredness of space –
it’s a back story –
and one that as with any
proposition – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
‘What do you mean if you say “space is coloured”?
(And, a very interesting question: what kind of question is this?) Well,
perhaps you look around for confirmation and look at different colours around
you and feel the inclination to say: “wherever I look there is a colour”, or
“it’s all coloured, all as it were painted.” Here you are imagining colours in
contrast to a colourlessness, which on closer inspection turns into a colour itself.
Incidentally, when you look around for confirmation you look first and foremost
at static monochromatic parts of space, rather than at unstable unclearly
coloured parts (flowing water, shadows, etc.). If you then have to admit that
you call just everything that you see colour, what you want to say is that
being coloured is a property of space in itself, not of parts of space. But
that comes to the same as saying
of chess that it is chess; and at best it can’t
amount to more than a description of the game. So what we must do is describe
spatial propositions; but we can’t justify them, as if we had to bring them
into agreement with an independent reality.’
I describe what I see as ‘coloured’ – I point out
colours – I refer to colours –
perhaps too – I use the term ‘colourless’ – in
certain contexts –
and if you ask me what these colour propositions
mean – I will have a go at accounting for them – I will put forward proposals
and you might keep at it with questions – with
doubts –
and I will try to answer your question – and
address your doubts
this process of proposal and question can go on as
long as there is breath to breathe
all we do in such analysis is explore propositional
possibilities –
we explore uncertainty
and if we stop doing this and just proceed with
whatever proposal we find useful at the time – that is what we do –
we proceed in uncertainty
yes – you describe i.e. spatial propositions – in
whatever way you do describe them –
and any so called ‘justification’ – is no more than
your argument for your account –
open to question – open to doubt – uncertain
independent reality – is reality independent of
description – of proposal – is the unknown
you can only propose that a proposition is in agreement –
with another proposition –
another proposal
‘In order to confirm the proposition “the visual field is
coloured ‘one looks around and says ‘that there is black, and black is a
colour; that is white, and white is a colour”, etc. And one regards “black is a
colour” as like “iron is a metal” (or perhaps
better, “gypsum is a sulphur compound”).’
yes – and as simple as that –
but confirmation is what?
putting the to and fro of argument aside here for the
moment–
confirmation – if it amounts to anything is – use
‘If I make it senseless to say that a part of my visual
field has a colour, then asking for the analysis of a statement assigning the
number of colours in a part of the visual space becomes very like asking for
the analysis of a statement of the number of parts of a rectangle that I divide
up into parts by lines.’
yes –
if the proposal is that a part of my visual field has no
colour – then assigning a number of colours in a part of my visual field – is
just to assign numbers –
dividing a rectangle into parts – just is a mathematical
action
and is the point here that assigning numbers is a game that
can be played however the context is described –
and is therefore an action that can be performed – is performed – regardless of so called empirical
consideration?
we can play the mathematical game however the world is –
and mathematics tells us nothing about the world – except
that we play these games –
we play games – and we question – is that the sum of it?
‘Here too I regard it as senseless to say that the
rectangle “consists of no parts”. Hence, one cannot say that it consists of one
or more parts, or that it has at least one
part. Imagine the special case of a rectangle divided by parallel lines. It
doesn’t matter that this is a very special case, since we don’t regard a game
as less remarkable just because it has only a limited application. Here I can
if I want count the parts in the usual manner, and then it is meaningless to
say there are 0 parts. But I could also imagine a way of counting which so to
say regards the first part as a matter of course and doesn’t count it as 0, and
counts only the parts that are added to this division. Again one could imagine
a custom according to which, say, soldiers in rank and file were always counted
by giving the number of soldiers in a line over and above the first soldier
(perhaps because we wanted the number of possible combinations of fuglemen with
another soldier of the rank). But a custom could also exist of always giving
the number of soldiers as 1 greater than the real one. Perhaps this happened
originally in order to deceive a particular officer about the real number, and
latter came into general use as a way of counting soldiers. (The academic
quarter). The number of different colours on a surface might also be given by
the number of their possible combinations in pairs and in that case the only
numbers that would count would be numbers of the form n/2(n-1); it would be as
senseless then to talk of the 2 or 4 colours of a surface as it is now to talk
of the Ö2
or i colours. I want to say that it is not the case that the cardinal numbers
are essentially primary and what we might call the combination numbers – 1, 2,
6, 10 etc. are secondary. We might construct an arithmetic of the combination
numbers and it would be as self-contained as the arithmetic of the cardinal
numbers. But equally of course there might be an arithmetic of the even numbers
or of the numbers 1, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7 …Of course the system is ill adapted for the
writing of these kinds of number.’
it is not that it is senseless to say that the
rectangle ‘consists of no parts’ – it is just that if you play the ‘game of
parts’ – then a ‘game of no parts’ – has no place –
in another context – a ‘non-part context’ – it will
have legs
‘But I could also imagine a way of counting which
so to say regards the first part as a matter of course and doesn’t count it as
0, and counts only the parts that are added to this division.’ –
yes – another
game of calculation
‘But a custom could also exist of always giving the
number of soldiers as 1 greater than the real one. Perhaps this happened
originally in order to deceive a particular officer about the real number, and
latter came into general use as a way of counting soldiers. (The academic
quarter).’ –
and again – a different
calculation game –
look whatever mathematical game you are playing –
will determine – the games you are not playing – it is that straightforward
to play a game – and then refer to another game as
‘senseless’ – is really just over- doing it –
the point of any game is its utility –
and just when a game is useful is any player’s
guess – is any player’s decision
cardinality is a number game –
as to cardinal numbers being essentially ‘primary’
–
which game is primary – will be a matter of focus
the ‘primary game’ will be determined by what is at
the time – in play
‘Imagine a calculating machine that calculates not with
beads but with colours on a strip of paper. Just as we now use our fingers, or
the beads on an abacus, to count the colours on a strip so then we would use
the colours on the strip to count the beads on a bar or the fingers on our
hand. But how would this colour-calculating machine have to be made in order to
work? We would need a sign for there being no bead on that bar. We must imagine
the abacus as a practical tool and as an instrument of language. Just as we now
represent a number like 5 by five fingers of a hand (imagine a gesture
language) so we would then represent it as a strip with five colours. But I
need the sign for the 0, otherwise I do not have the necessary multiplicity.
Well I can either stipulate that a black surface is to denote the 0 (this of
course is arbitrary and a monochromatic red surface would do just as well); or
that any one coloured surface is to denote zero, a two coloured surface 1, etc.
It is immaterial which method of denotation I choose. Here we see that the
multiplicity of the beads is projected onto the multiplicity of the colours on
a surface’
yes it is immaterial which method of denotation I use –
the denotation – the game – must be defined – must be
determined
and in the mode of game design – as distinct from the mode
of game play –
we are in the realm of uncertainty –
any proposal put forward – i.e. method of denotation – rules
to use etc. –
is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
when decisions are made – we have a game –
we have a play
‘It makes no sense to speak
of a black two sided figure in a white circle; this is analogous to its being
senseless to say that the rectangle consists of 0 parts (no part). Here we have
something like a lower limit of counting before we reach the number one.’
a black two sided figure in
a white circle – senseless?
it depends how you define
‘figure’ –
consider two sides of an
equilateral triangle drawn in black– which is to say two lines – where of
course the figure is not solid – nevertheless a black two sided figure?
as for a rectangle having
no parts –
this is not senseless – it
is just a possible description –
another possible
description is that the rectangle has parts
it really depends on
what you want to do with the rectangle
it’s a question – once
again of defining your game
the rectangle – has no
properties – outside of the properties ascribed
to it –
how the rectangle is to be
described – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
how the rectangle will be
described – will be a function of the propositional context in which it is to
figure
its description will be a function of the
argument of that context

‘Is counting parts in I the
same as counting points in IV? What makes the difference? We may regard
counting the parts in I as counting rectangles; but in that case one can also
say: “in this row there is no
rectangle”; and the one isn’t counting parts.
We are disturbed both by the analogy between counting the points and counting
the parts, and by the breakdown of the analogy.’
look – you have to decide
what it is you’re counting –
so it is a question of
which description you are using – i.e. parts or rectangles
once that issue is decide –
the analogy – if you want there to be an analogy here – holds –
as to the counting – in the
end it makes no difference to the count – how you describe what you count –
the counting game – as such
– really has nothing to do with what is counted –
however the counting game
will have different descriptions i.e. ‘counting parts’ – ‘counting rectangles’
– ‘counting points’ –
you are not going to have a
game –
if you don’t know what
you’re counting
‘There is something odd in
counting the undivided surface as “one”; on the other hand we find no
difficulty in seeing the surface after a single division as a picture of 2.
Here we would much prefer to count “ 0, 2, 3”, etc. And this corresponds to the
series of “the rectangle is undivided”, “the rectangle is divided into 2
parts”, etc.’
it doesn’t matter whether
its odd or not –
the issue is defining the
counting game
yes ‘0’ – can be correlated with ‘the rectangle is undivided’
– but so what?
we could well decide that
yes the undivided surface is ‘one’ – and quite naturally speak of the divided
surface as 2
and so 1 and 2 are the only
numbers in this game –
and therefore 0 – is not in
the game –
and so for the purpose of
the game – I’m afraid to say – 0 doesn’t exist –
shock horror
‘If it’s a question of
different colours, you can imagine a way of thinking in which you don’t say
that here we have two colours, but that here we have a distinction between
colours; a style of thought which does not see 3 at all in red, green and
yellow; which does indeed recognize as a series a series like: red: blue,
green: yellow, black, white: etc., but doesn’t connect it with the series |; ||; |||;
etc., or in such a way as to correlate | with the term red.’
yes – of course
‘From the point of view from which it is ‘odd’ to
count the undivided surface as one, it
is also natural to count the singly divided one as two. That is what one does
if one regards it as two rectangles, and that would mean looking at it from the
standpoint from which the undivided one might well be counted as one rectangle.
But if one regards the first rectangle in I as the undivided surface, then the
second appears as a whole with one division (one distinction) and division here
does not necessarily mean dividing line. What I am paying attention to is the
distinctions, and here there is a series of an increasing number of
distinctions. In that case I will count the rectangles in I “0, 1, 2, etc.”
This is all right where the colours on a strip border
on each other, as in the schema

But it is different if the arrangement is

or

Of course I might also correlate each of these two
schemata with the schema

and correlate schemata like

with

etc. And that way of thinking though perfectly
unnatural is perfectly correct.
The most natural thing is conceive the series as

etc. And here we may denote
the first schema by ‘0’, the second by ‘1’, but the third say with ‘3’, if we
think of all possible distinctions, and the fourth by ‘6’. Or we may call the
third schema ‘2’ (if we are concerned simply with an arrangement) and the
fourth ‘3’.’
here we have games of
correlation –
and as with any game you
have to decide its rule –
then the question is how
far can you take the game –
i.e. what proposed
correlations work and what proposed correlations don’t work –
relative to the rule
decided
and of course you can
always experiment with different rules –
different rules different
correlations – different games – different plays
‘We can describe the way a
triangle is divided by saying: it is divided into five parts, or: 4 parts have
been cut off it, or: its division-schema is ABCDE, or: you can reach every part
by crossing four boundaries; or the rectangle is divided (i.e. into 2 parts),
one part is divided again, and both parts of
this part divided, etc. I want to show that there isn’t only one method of describing the way it is
divided.’

yes – there isn’t any one
method of describing the way the triangle is divided –
and in so far as we explore
different possible descriptions – the game as such is an exploration of
possible descriptions
a rule to play yes – but
the rule – its range – its application –
is open to question –
the rule is only as it were
fixed – when the questioning stops – when the exploration comes to an end
such is not a logical end –
rather a pragmatic beginning
‘But perhaps we might
refrain altogether from using a number to denote distinction and keep solely to
the schemata A, AB, ABC, etc. or we might describe it like this: 1, 12, 123
etc., or, what comes to the same, 0, 01, 012 etc.
We may very well call these
too numerals.’
any description – any
denotation – any game – works – if works –
that is to say – if it
functions in a propositional context –
and for a propositional
context to function –
its terms and argument must
be explainable or recognizable to those who participate in that context –
even though shadowing the
proceeding – will be question – doubt –and uncertainty
that is just the way of it
.
‘The schemata A, AB, ABC
etc, ½, ½½, ½½½,
etc; 


yes ‘fundamental’ –
not a term that we need any
more – certainly not in logic –
however it is quite functional
in rhetoric
we operate with our
proposals – that is our propositions – and our proposals – whatever they are –
are open to question – open to doubt –
are uncertain
‘We are surprised that the
number-schema by which we count soldiers in a barracks isn’t supposed to hold
for the parts of a rectangle. But the schema for the soldiers in the barracks
is

etc, the one for the parts
of the rectangle is

etc. neither is primary in
comparison with the other.
I can compare the series of
division-schemata with the series 1, 2, 3, etc. as well as with the series 0,
1, 2, 3, etc.
If I count the parts, then
there is no 0 in any number series because the series

etc. begins with one letter
whereas the series
etc.
does not begin with one dot. On the
other hand, I can represent any fact about the division by this series too,
only in that case “I’m not counting the parts”.’

the proposal that counting
soldiers in a barracks isn’t supposed to hold for the parts of a rectangle – is
– as with any proposal – open to question
Wittgenstein in the above
argument puts forward a representation that illustrates a correspondence
and yes – if the aim of the
game is to show a correspondence – then the game must be defined in such a way
that facilitates this goal.
and as Wittgenstein shows
above – even though in the lettered series – the series begins with one letter
– whereas in the dot series – it doesn’t begin with one dot –
any fact about the division
by this series can be represented too– so long as the game is not defined as ‘counting parts’
and so we have a correspondence – if the game is not defined as counting parts’
the logical point here is that definition of the
game – is – and must be – open to question –
otherwise you run the risk of missing all the fun
‘A way of expressing the problem which, though
incorrect, is natural is: why can one say “there are 2 colours on this surface”
but not “there is one colour on this surface?”
Or how can I express the
grammatical rule so that it is obvious and so that I’m not tempted to talk
nonsense? Where is the false thought, the false analogy by which I am misled
into misusing language? How must I get the grammar so that the temptation
ceases? I think that setting it out by means of the series

removes the unclarity.
What matters is whether in
order to count I use the number series that begins with 0 or one that begins
with 1.
It is the same if I am
counting the lengths of sticks or the size of hats.
If I counted with strokes
the lengths of I might write them thus


all that is at issue here is understanding that a
proposition is a proposal – and as such is open to question – open to
interpretation –
and that in mathematics – there is in fact as much
propositional uncertainty – or flexibility – as there is any propositional
activity
and as for –
‘nonsense’ –
nonsense is the proposal – that is held to be
beyond question – beyond doubt
there is no misuse of language – there is only
different uses –
‘false thought’?
a so called ‘false thought’ – will be a proposal
that it is argued doesn’t fit in the broader propositional context under
consideration –
note I said ‘argued’ – for any proposal is logically speaking open
to question
yes we make decisions as to what proposals we will
use – but that is just pragmatics
a ‘false thought’ – will be a proposal – you decide
not to use
and let’s get off the God truck – and recognize
that there will be many uses of language
– of signs – that we will be confronted with – that initially – we don’t
understand
and yes we have to work to get an understanding –
and the truth of the matter is – we can never be
sure – we’ve got it – or indeed – ‘what getting it’ amounts to –
and further this uncertainty – has stopped no one –
and is in fact the very engine of exploration and
creativity
‘Here incidentally there is a certain difficulty
about the numerals (1), ((1) + 1), etc:
beyond a certain length we cannot distinguish them
any further without counting the strokes, and so without translating the signs
into different ones. “||||||||||”
and “|||||||||||”
cannot be distinguished in the same sense as 10 and
11, and so they aren’t in the same sense distinct signs. The same thing could
also happen incidentally in the decimal system (think of the numbers 1111111111
and 11111111111), and that is not without significance.’
yes – if and when this becomes a difficulty that
inhibits propositional action – we make arrangements –
i.e. we modify the sign game we are playing – or we
devise a new sign system – a new game
‘Imagine someone giving us a sum to do in a
stroke-notation, say |||||||||| +|||||||||||,
and, while we are calculating, amusing himself by removing and adding strokes
without our noticing. He would keep saying: “ but the sum isn’t right”, and we
would keep going through it again, fooled every time. – Indeed, strictly
speaking, we wouldn’t have any concept of a criterion for the correctness of
the calculation’
as presented – this game is being sabotaged
hence – no game – no calculation
either that – or we in fact have another ‘game’ in
the guise of the expected or standard game –
and without rules for it – no game –
if there are rules and the player doesn’t know them
– or comes to realize he doesn’t know them –
he should wake up to himself
‘Here one might raise questions like: is it only very probable that 464 + 272 = 736? And
in that case isn’t 2 + 3 = 5 also very probable? And where is the objective
truth which this probability approaches? That is, how do we get a concept of 2
+ 3’s really being a certain number,
apart from what it seems to us to
be?’
the issue here is what game are you playing?
2 + 3 = 5 is not a probability game
2 + 3 = 5
how do we get this objective truth?
this ‘objective truth’ is nothing more than a sign
game – a rule governed game –
that
is in use
2 + 3 = 5 – is an example of – or representation of
– a propositional practice –
that has had and continues to have endorsement –
primarily because of its utility
in any case we can say arithmetic is a cultural
practise – and its history is ancient
the same can be said of probability games – but
arithmetic’s is not a probability game
here we have different games –
and there is no value is confusing the two
‘For if we were asked: what is the criterion in the
stroke-notation for our having the same numeral in front of us twice? – the
answer might be: “if it looks the same both times”. Or should it be: if a
one-one correlation etc. is possible?’
yes there are different ways of answering the question
–
the reality is that in the end what we have is a propositional practise –
and as with any propositional practice – how you
account for it – how you explain it –
is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
such is propositional reality
‘How can I know that ||||||||||
and ||||||||||
are the same sign? After all it is
not enough that they look alike. For
having roughly the same gestalt can’t be what is to constitute the identity of
the signs, but just their being the same in number.’
what is to constitute the identity of signs?
‘identity’ as with any other proposal – is open to
question – open to doubt – is uncertain
so could we run with the gestalt?
I think yes –
would such a view of identity work in a
mathematical context
I think not
in the mathematical context – you do the count
‘(The problem of the distinction between 1 +1 + 1 +
1 + 1 + 1 + 1 and 1 +1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1 is much more fundamental than
appears at first sight. It is a matter of the distinction between physical and
visual number.)’
physical and visual?
is there any distinction here?
19. 2 +2 = 4
‘A cardinal number is an internal property of a list.’
a cardinal number is a use of the number game –
it is an application of numbers on numbers –
a number game played with numbers
a ‘list’ – is a description of propositions – of proposals –
a ‘list’ is a description
–
‘an internal property’ –
of a list’?
is a description – of a description –
and what of such a description?
it is to say that a list has an ‘internality’ –
a ‘dimension’ – distinguishable apparently from its
– ‘external’ – dimension
I think this loads up the ‘list’ with unnecessary –
totally unnecessary – baggage
we have a proposal –‘the list’ –
and then a further proposal – the cardinal number –
in relation to that proposal
one proposal in relation to another
that’s all there is to it
‘internal’ / ‘external’ here – descriptions
reminiscent of outdated epistemology and metaphysics
yes you can go there – by all means – look – you can
go wherever you like –
but to my mind – doing so – makes what is
essentially a straightforward matter of propositional action – into a rather
woolly metaphysical concern –
and the fact is you can avoid going down this path
–
so why not?
‘Are numbers essentially concerned with concepts?’
numbers are signs in a counting game – if they are
anything at all –
the issue (if there is an issue) is not numbers –
the issue is the action of counting – is the counting game
it is the counting game we describe – by the use of
terms such as ‘numbers’
it is entirely irrelevant – how you describe – what you count – ‘numbers’ – ‘concepts’ –
‘objects’ – whatever –
it is the action of counting – the game of counting that is relevant –
it is the doing
of it that is the point of it –
description – is up for grabs
‘I believe this amounts to asking whether it makes
sense to ascribe a number to objects that haven’t been brought under a
concept?’
whether you bring objects under a concept or not –
and that is just a way of describing objects – of dealing with objects – is
irrelevant to whether you ‘ascribe a number’ or not –
the number game is played – can be played –
regardless of context –
that is regardless of descriptive context –
if your descriptive context is ‘objects under
concept’ – you can of course play the number game in this context
if your descriptive context is something else – the
same applies –
‘The concept is only a method for determining an
extension, but the extension is autonomous and, in its essence, independent of
the concept; for its quite immaterial which concept we have used to determine
the extension. This is the argument for the extensional viewpoint. The
immediate argument against it is: if a concept is really only an expedient for aiming
at an extension, then there is no place for concepts in arithmetic; in that
case we must simply divorce a class completely from the concept which happens
to be associated with it. But if it isn’t like that then an extension
independent of a concept is just a chimaera, and in that case it’s better not
to speak of it at all, but only of the concept.’
the ‘extension’ is a set of proposals – that it is
proposed are related in a particular manner to an initial proposal
all we have here is individual proposals – and a proposal relating
the individual proposals –
the term ‘extension’ may be used to describe this
language-game –
but that is all it is – a description of a kind of
propositional game –
as for ‘concept –
yes a concept is an organising principle – a description of a proposal for organising
– propositions –
all very well – but not the main game
Wittgenstein goes on to say –
‘The sign for the extension of a concept is a list.
We might say as an approximation that a number is an external property of its
extension (the list of objects that fall under it). A number is a schema for
the extension of a concept. That is, as Frege said, a statement of a number is
a statement about a concept (a predicate). It is not about the extension of a
concept, i.e. a list that might be something like the extension of a concept.
But a number-statement about a concept has a similarity to a proposition saying
that a determinate list is the extension of the concept. I use such a list when
I say “a, b, c, d, fall under the concept F(x)”: “a, b, c, d,” is the list. Of
course this proposition says the same as Fa.Fb.Fc.Fd; but the use of the list
in writing the proposition shows its relationship to “($x,
y, z, u). Fx. Fy. Fz. Fu” which we can abbreviate as “($½½½½x).F(x).”
’
‘The sign for the extension of a concept is a list’
–
a ‘list’ is a description
of propositions
a number – as an external property of its
extension?
a number is a point in a number-game – a mark of
action – if indeed there is any need to mark the action
to speak of numbers – outside of number games – is
where you go wrong
the central focus is not number – but the
number-game
if you wish to describe the game – yes – you can
describe it in terms of the action of
numbers
‘a number as a schema for the extension of a
concept’
the number game is played in various contexts –
settings –
if you use the description ‘concept’ – you can run
the game in that descriptive context – but this is to say nothing about the
number-game as such – it is just a reference to a context of use
‘That is, as Frege said, a statement of a number is
a statement about a concept (predicate). It is not about the extension of a
concept. But a number-statement about a concept has a similarity to a
proposition saying that a determinate list is the extension of the concept.’
this kind of rigmarole is just what results from
failing to understand mathematics
yes – you play with chess pieces – but they have no
value as chess pieces – outside of the chess
game
by all means come up with different proposals to
describe what you are working with and different descriptions for how you have
organized what you are working with i.e.
– ‘concepts’ –‘extensions’ –
but these descriptions have nothing to do with the
number-game
a number-statement by the way is not mathematics –
is not the numbers game – and is essentially irrelevant to it
it is a propositional use of the numbers-game – a
description that uses the number-game
where the focus is the number – you have well and
truly left mathematics – taken yourself out
of the game
Frege wallows in descriptive metaphysics –
I have no objection to him proposing a view of
reality – and stitching it up nicely –
with whatever descriptions and arguments fit his
view
but I would argue that in so doing he
misunderstands and misuses mathematics
any proposition – any proposal is open to question
– open to doubt
however when we play propositional games –
the point of the game – be mathematics or some
other game – is that it is a rule governed propositional activity
when you play – if you play – you play – without
question – without doubt – in accordance with the rules – whatever they might
be
this is what human beings do – propose – and – play
we propose and we play – logically different
activities –
best not to confuse the two
‘What arithmetic is concerned with is the schema ½½½½.
– But does arithmetic talk about the lines I draw with pencil on paper? –
Arithmetic doesn’t talk about the lines, it operates with them.’
yes – exactly
‘If you want to know what 2 + 2 = 4 means, you have
to ask how we work it out. That means that we consider the process of
calculation as the essential thing; and that’s how we look at the matter in
ordinary life, at least as far as concerns the numbers that we have to work
out. We mustn’t feel ashamed of regarding numbers and sums in the same way as
the everyday arithmetic of every trader. In everyday life we don’t work out 2 +
2 = 4 or any of the rules of the multiplication table; we take them for granted
like axioms and use them to
calculate. But of course we could work out 2 + 2 = 4 and children in fact do so
by counting off. Given the sequence of numbers 12345 the calculation is 1 2 1 2
1 2 3 4’
‘If you want to know what 2 + 2 = 4 means, you have
to ask how we work it out.’ –
yes – you have to be introduced into the game – and
you have to be shown – how to play it
– by whatever means
what you are being shown is the game – and game playing
and does anyone really ask what the game playing means?
‘what’s it mean to play a game?’ – ‘here – watch’
and this may sound like no answer at all – but the
fact is we play it – because play is
a basic human activity – it is what we do
it is what we do – in language – we play
language-games
and mathematics is a central game
‘That means that we consider the process of
calculation as the essential thing; and that’s how we look at the matter in
ordinary life, at least as far as concerns the numbers that we have to work
out.’
yes the process of calculation is the essential
thing
‘the process of calculation’ – is the game play
I can show
you how the game is played – or different ways of playing it – and that is
the ‘explanation’ –
the
play
‘The difference between my point of view and that
of contemporary writers on the foundations of arithmetic is that I am not
obliged to despise particular calculi like the decimal system. For me one
calculus is as good as another. To look down on a particular calculus is like
wanting to play chess without real pieces, because playing with pieces is too
particularized and not abstract enough. If the pieces really don’t matter then
one lot is as good, i.e. as interesting, as another. And if the games are
really distinct from each other, then one game is as good, i.e. as interesting,
as another. None of them is more sublime than the other.’
yes – exactly –
there is no reason not to have an open mind – and
to be flexible –
you can play with whatever ‘pieces’ suit you under
the circumstances –
and play is play –
whatever the game – it is the play that is sublime
‘Which proof of ∊ ½½. ∊ ½½½. É .
½½½½½
expresses our knowledge that this is a correct logical proposition?
Obviously, one that makes use of the fact that one
can treat ($x)
… as a logical sum. We may translate … [this proposition] “if there is a star
in each square, then there are two in the whole rectangle” into the Russellian
one. And it isn’t as if the tautologies in that notation expressed an idea that
is confirmed by the proof after first of all appearing plausible; what appears
plausible to us is that this expression is a tautology (a law of logic).’
a ‘correct logical proposition’ –
that will depend on what logic – what language-game
is being played – and how it is played – according to its rules – or not
a proof is a language game – principally an
argument whereby p is derived from premises
a tautology is a repetition – if that is a ‘law of
logic’ – so be it
plausibility?
what is plausible is a proposal – a proposition –
open to question – open to doubt –
uncertain
the form of the tautology – or at least how it is
traditionally represented – is quite the opposite to this –
and yet you wouldn’t grace it with description
‘implausible’ –
the tautology has use as a word game – a game of
redundancy –
but as a proposition – as a proposal it is
malformed – like an animal born with two heads
Wittgenstein goes on to consider the
adequacy of Russellian notation – Russellian proposals – relative to ordinary
language proposals – and it is clear from Wittgenstein’s argument that
Russellian notation – as with any other propositional form is open to question
– open to doubt – is uncertain
‘ “($3 x, y). F(x, y)” would perhaps
correspond to the proposition in word-language “F(x, y) is satisfied by 3
things”; and that the proposition too would need an explanation if it was not
to be ambiguous.
Am I now to say that in these different cases the
sign “3” has different meanings? Isn’t it rather that the sign “3” expresses
what is common to the different interpretations? Why else would I have chosen
it? Certainly in each of these contexts,
the same rules hold for the sign “3”. It is
replaceable by 2 + 1 as usual and so on. But at all events a proposition on the
pattern of ∊ ½½. ∊ ½½½. É .
∊ ½½½½½
is no longer a tautology. Two men who live at peace with each other do not make
five men who live at peace with each other. But that does not mean 2 + 3 are no
longer 5; it is just that addition cannot be applied in that way. For one might
say: 2 men who … and 3 men who …, each
of whom lives at peace with each other of the first group, = 5 men who …
In other words. the signs of the form ($1x,
y) . F(x, y), ($2x,y)
. F (x, y) etc. have the same multiplicity as the cardinal numbers, like the
signs ($1x)
. jx,
($2x)
. jx
etc. and also like the signs (∊ 1x) . jx,
(∊ 2 x) . jx,
etc.
‘ “($3 x, y). F(x, y)” would perhaps
correspond to the proposition in word-language “F(x, y) is satisfied by 3
things”; and that the proposition too would need an explanation if it was not
to be ambiguous’. –
the point here is that the proposal – the
proposition ‘($3 x, y). F(x, y) – as with the
proposal – the proposition – ‘F(x, y) is satisfied by 3 things’ – is open to
question – open to doubt – is uncertain
‘Am I now to say that in these different cases the
sign “3” has different meanings?’
if it’s the same game played across different
proposals – different contexts – then it’s the same game –
and that’s all very well – but any proposal – any
proposition – and the terms of any proposition – are open to question – to
doubt – are – logically speaking – uncertain
you may decide to regard a term as ‘the same’ in
different proposals – (this is what you do when you play number games) – but
playing a language-game with regard to propositions – is not ‘the same’ as
regarding them logically – that is – as – open to question – open to doubt – as
uncertain
cardinality is a numbers game – and yes – this game
can be played across different
propositions –
and that you might say – is the point of it
‘ “There are only 4 red things, but they don’t
consist of 2 and 2, as there is no function under which they fall in pairs”.
That would mean regarding the proposition 2 + 2 = 4 thus: if you can see 4
circles on a surface, every two of them always have a particular property in
common; say a sign inside the circle. (In that case of course every three of
the circles too will have to have a sign in common etc.) If I am to make any
assumption at all about reality, why not that?
The ‘axiom of reducibility’ is essentially the same kind of thing. In this
sense one might say that 2 and 2 always make 4. (It isn’t only because of the
utter vagueness and generality of the axiom of reducibility that we are seduced
into believing that – if it is a significant sentence at all – it is more than
an arbitrary assumption for which there is no ground. For this reason, in this
and in all similar cases, it is very illuminating to drop this generality,
which doesn’t make the matter any more mathematical, and in its place to make
very specific assumptions.)’
‘If I am to make any assumption at all about
reality, why not that?’ –
yes if it suits your purpose
reality is propositional
– that is what is proposed – and any proposal – any proposition – is open to
question – open to doubt – is uncertain
that 2 + 2 = 4 – is a mathematical game – that can
be played in whatever context it is played in
if regarded as ‘a sentence’ – a proposal – a
proposition – it is open to question – to doubt – is uncertain –
the different logical uses or modes of language –
are the proposal (proposition) –
and the game
language as a game – that is a rule governed
activity – and the use of language as proposal
– language – open to question – open to doubt – uncertain – language if you
like – in the absence of rules
Wittgenstein does not understand the difference –
the difference between the game – and the proposition – and as a consequence –
confuses the two
this ‘axiom of reducibility’ – is a proposal – open
to question – open to doubt – uncertain –
this is clear from Wittgenstein’s own work in the Tractatus (6.1233) - Zermelo (1908) – Wiener (1914) and indeed
Russell himself in his 19217 Introduction
to the second edition of ‘Principia
Mathematica’ –
the point is that if this proposal is useful – for
whatever philosophical agenda – it will have a run
as for ‘an arbitrary assumption for which there is
no ground’ –
the ground of any assumption is its use –
and some will ask – what ground is that?
all you can put here is – the argument or arguments
for use –
and any such argument – whatever it might be –
is a back story – is rhetoric –
the world we operate in – is what is – proposed –
and what is proposed – reality – if you like –
is groundless
‘We feel like saying: 4 does not always have to
consist of 2 and 2, but if it does consist of groups it can consist of 2 and 2
or of 3 and 1 two; but not of 2 and 1 or 3 and 2, etc. In that way we get
everything prepared in case 4 is actually divisible into groups. But in that
case arithmetic doesn’t have anything to do with the actual 268.
division, but only with the possibility of
division. The assertion might just as well be the assertion that any two of a
group of 4 dots on paper are always joined by a line.
Or that around every 2 such groups of 2 dots in the
real world there is always a circle drawn.’
games can be played within games –
and yes the promise of any well constructed game –
is possibility –
asking what does the game allow – is not
questioning the game – it is exploring
the game
a game – as such is not to be confused with a
proposal – a proposition – what Wittgenstein refers to here – as an ‘assertion’
–
a proposal is not a game –
a proposal – is open to question – open to doubt –
is uncertain –
yes – you can propose that – ‘around every 2 such
groups of 2 dots in the real world there is always a circle drawn.’
good luck with that
‘Add to this that a statement
like “you can see two black circles in a white rectangle” doesn’t have the form
“($x,
y), etc. For, if I give the circles names, the names refer to the precise
location of the circles, and I can’t say of them that they are either in this
rectangle or in the other. I can indeed say “there are 4 circles in both
rectangles taken together” but that doesn’t mean that I can say of an
individual circle that it is in one rectangle or the other. For in the case
supposed “this circle is in this triangle” is senseless.’
‘you can see two black circles in a white
rectangle’ – doesn’t have the form ‘($x, y)’ –
and I guess you take from this that translation
from one propositional form to another – is not without contention –
you go from one proposition – to another –
and any such move is best seen not as ‘translation’
– rather as propositional exploration
some call it the indeterminacy of translation – and
that is not a bad start – but really you are dealing here with different propositions –
at any time with any proposition – any proposal –
the logical reality – is the reality of uncertainty –
so called ‘translation’ – is no special case –
we move from proposition to proposition – in the
context of uncertainty – in any propositional activity
‘For, if I give the circles names, the names refer
to the precise location of the circles, and I can’t say of them that they are
either in this rectangle or in the other.’ –
actually – it doesn’t follow that naming the
circles – gives precise location of
the circles –
and you could say which rectangle they are in –
with further description –
you could nominate one square as coloured red – the
other green
and I can’t see why you couldn’t do the same with
the circles –
in so doing – of course you have modified the
original description (‘two black circles in a white rectangle’ etc) –
but if the question is to do with distinction –
this is what you need to do –
otherwise don’t carry on about distinguishing them
the general point is that any proposal – any
proposition – is uncertain – is open to question – is open to doubt –
and therefore the pursuit of precision – as
certainty – is logical nonsense –
we operate with uncertain propositions – and we explore this uncertainty –
‘this circle is in this triangle’ – is not senseless
–
the question is – does it function in this context?
‘But what does the proposition “there are 4 circles
in the 2 rectangles taken together” mean? How do I establish that? By adding
the numbers in each? In that case the number of circles in two rectangles means the result of the addition of the
two numbers. – Or is it something like the result of taking a count through
both triangles? Or the number of lines I get if I correlate a line to a circle
no matter whether it is in this rectangle or
in the other? If “this circle” is
individuated by its position, we can say “every line is correlated either to a
circle in this rectangle or to a circle in the other rectangle” but not “this
circle is either in this rectangle or in the other” This can only be here if “this” and “here” do not mean the same. By
contrast this line can be correlated
to a circle in this rectangle because it remains this line, even if it is
correlated to a circle in the other rectangle.’
‘But what does the proposition “there are 4 circles
in the 2 rectangles taken together” mean? How do I establish that? –
what it means – is how it is used –
and any use is open to question – open to doubt –
is uncertain
how do I ‘establish’ that?
establish? – you use it in some propositional context –
use – is all ‘establish’ can come to
the proposition – ‘there are 4 circles in the 2
rectangles taken together’ – as with any proposal – is open to question – open
to doubt – is uncertain –
which is to say – open to interpretation –
and what you get from Wittgenstein in what follows
above (‘By adding … triangle’) –
is just that – interpretation – argument

‘In these two circles together there are 9 dots or
7? As one normally understands the question, 7. But must I understand it so?
Why shouldn’t I count twice the points that are common to both circles?’
the point is there is an argument –
the proposal – the pictorial proposition – is open
to question – open to doubt – is uncertain –
and obviously so – its logic – is not hidden – it
is revealed –
there is no rhetorical packaging – it is plain –
for all to see
here we have a fine display of propositional
reality
a good illustration

‘It is a different matter if we ask “how many dots
are within the black lines?” For here I can say: in the sense in which there
are 5 and 4 in the circles, there are 7.’
yes – as the form of the question is specific –
i.e. the black lines

‘Now we might say: by the sum of 4 and 5 I mean the
number of the objects which fall under the concept jx v yx, if it is the case that (E
4x) . jx.(
E
5x) . yx
. Ind.
That doesn’t mean that the sum of 4 and 5 may only be used in the context of
propositions like ($
4x) . jx;
it means: if you want to construct the sum of n and m, insert the numbers on
the left hand side of “É”
in the form ($nx)
. jx
. ($mx)
. yx,
etc. and the sum of m and n will be the number which has to go on the right
hand side in order to make the whole proposition a tautology. So that is a
method of addition – a very long-winded one.’
yes – again – there is no ambiguity –
and as for the ‘construction’ – the ‘tautology’ – a
language-game – as explanation of a language-game –
however – if you understand the game – its
logic – to begin with – what need any
further ‘explanation’?
it’s really just a restatement in another form –
as if such has any ‘deeper’ meaning – any logical
significance – beyond ‘4 +5 = 9’!
‘Compare: Hydrogen and oxygen yield water”, “2 dots
and 3 dots yield 5 dots”.’
here we have two proposals – open to question – open to doubt – and uncertain –
i.e. just what are we to make of ‘yield’ – in both
proposals?
‘So do e.g. 2 dots in my visual field, that I “see
as 4” and not “as 2 and 2” consist of 2 and 2? Well what does that mean? Is it
asking whether in some way they are divided into groups of 2 dots each? Of
course not (for in that case they would presumably have had to be divided in
all other conceivable ways as well). Does it mean that they can be divided into groups of 2 and 2,
i.e. that it makes sense to speak of
such groups in the four? – At any rate it does correspond to the sentence 2 + 2
= 4 that I can’t say that the group of 4 dots I saw consisted of separate
groups of 2 and 3. Everyone will say: That’s “impossible”, because 3 + 2 = 5.
(And impossible here means “nonsensical”.)’
2 dots in my visual field that I see as 4 –
are 4 dots in my visual field – not 2
if I see them as 2 and 2 – then I have applied a
mathematical game to what I see –
and this I did too – when I described what I saw as
‘4’ –
‘is it asking whether in some way they are divided
into groups of 2 dots each?’ –
if you apply the division game here – yes ‘in some
way’ they are divided into groups of 2 dots each –
dividing them into groups of 2 dots each – is a way
of describing what you see – a way of dealing with what you see –
and presumably playing this game is of some use to
you –
‘of course not (for in that case they would
presumably have had to be divided in all other conceivable ways as well)’ –
no – they don’t have
to be divided in all conceivable ways –
what has been done – the game that has been played
– is the division into groups of 2 dots each
‘does it mean that they can be divided into groups of 2 and 2, i.e. that it makes sense to speak of such groups in
the four?’
why not?
‘at any rate it does correspond to the sentence 2 +
2 = 4 that I can’t say that the group of 4 dots I saw consisted of separate
groups of 2 and 3’ –
correct – the numbers game here – has rules –
if you want to change the game – you have to change
the rules –
it would be an entirely different game
‘everyone will say: That’s “impossible”, because 3
+ 2 =5. (And impossible here means “nonsensical”.)’ –
‘3 + 2 = 5’ – has the form of a recognizable arithmetic game – but it is not a game we
understand given the present propositional context
as a proposal – it is open to question –
if you are to put that proposal – forward explain
what you are on about –
otherwise it is no more than an illustration – of not following the rules of the game
–
of not understanding accepted practise in a given
context
“Do 4 dots consist of 2 and 2?” may be a question
about a physical or visual fact; for it isn’t a question in arithmetic. The
arithmetical question, however, certainly could be put in the form: “Can a
group of 4 dots consist of separate groups of 2?”
‘do 4 dots consist of 2 and 2 may be a question
about a physical or visual fact’? –
‘the physical or visual fact’ – is the descriptive context – in which the
arithmetical question is asked
‘can a group of 4 consist of separate groups of 2?’
– is an arithmetical question – asked in the absence of descriptive context
let’s be clear here – asking an arithmetical question – is not doing arithmetic –
such questions are game questions – questions about
the game – the logic of the game the rules of the game –
if you do arithmetic
– you play the game
questioning the game – is not playing the game
‘ “Suppose that I used to believe that there wasn’t
anything at all except one function and four objects that satisfy it. Latter I
realise that it is satisfied by a fifth thing too: does that make the sign ‘4’
become senseless?” – well if there is no 4 in the calculus then ‘4’ is senseless.’
what you believe
– whatever that is – is open to question – open to doubt –
what you believe is uncertain
realizing latter that there is a fifth thing too – just
makes the point –
beliefs are proposals
‘does that make the sign ‘4’ become senseless?” –
well if there is no 4 in the calculus then
‘4’ is senseless’
what it means is that if you are going to continue
to play the arithmetical game – in the new
context – then presumably the terms of that game – will change to fit the context
in any case ‘senseless’ is way too harsh – and
somewhat stupid –
if a sign – a term – has a use – it has sense –
when it is not used – it is not it is senseless –
it is simply not
used
in what follows Wittgenstein considers the use of
the tautology when adding – and he
explains how it can be used
this is all very well but the point is that the
tautology game as applied to arithmetic – is no more than a restatement of the
arithmetic game – a restatement – that
in no way adds to the arithmetic game – or takes away from it – if the
tautology game is constructed successfully
symbolic logic – or some variant of it might provide an interesting structure – and lead
to interesting insights – but it is a language game – played on a language game
its basis is no different to the language it
describes –
and its ‘basis’ – as with the basis to any language
use – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
Wittgenstein goes on to look at proofs of
arithmetical game-propositions –
his ‘proofs’ simply amount to rewriting the
game-proposition – in some other form – as if this provides proof
let’s be clear we can completely dispense with this
notion of proof –
a game-proposition – is a proposition that is to be
understood in terms of the rules of the game
these rules of the game are accepted for the
purpose of playing the game –
if you are to play the game – play it –
if what you are on about is questioning the game –
question it – but don’t think that in so doing you are playing it
any proposal – any proposition is open to question
– open to doubt –
no game is –
that is the point of the game –
it is the point of play
‘It may sound odd, but it is good advice at this point;
don’t do philosophy here, do mathematics’
any mathematical game – begins with proposals and
involves the construction and the development of a language-game –
this is a speculative enterprise –
any such proposal – the utility of any such proposal
or set of proposals – is – open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain –
mathematicians have the final word here – it is a
question of what they regard as useful
to their practise
doing mathematics – is doing it – playing the game
– playing the games
the business of proposal and argument – is
philosophical –
and this is the case – in whatever context – whatever context –
you find proposal and argument
Wittgenstein goes on to consider calculus
construction –
this amounts to a discussion of language-game
construction –
and the business of fitting one language-game to
another –
this you might say is a game in itself – where
rules are resurrected or indeed new rules proposed –
and there is indeed art to all of this
‘A question that suggests itself is this: must we
introduce the cardinal numbers in connection with the notation ($x,
y, …) . fx.
fy
… ? Is the calculus of the cardinal numbers somehow bound up with the calculus
of the signs ($x,
y, …) . fx.
fy
… ?
Is that kind of calculus perhaps in the nature of
things the only application of cardinal numbers? So far as concerns the
“application of the cardinal numbers in the grammar”, we can refer to what we
said about the concept of the application of a calculus. We might put our
question in this way too: in the propositions of our language – if we imagine
them translated into Russell’s notation – do the cardinal numbers always occur
after the sign “$”?
This question is closely connected with another: Is a numeral always used in
language as a characterization of a concept – of a function? The answer to that
is that our language does always use the numerals as attributes of
concept-words – but that these concept-words belong to different grammatical
systems that are so totally distinct from each other (as you see from the fact
that some of them have meaning in contexts in which others are senseless), that
a norm making them all concept-words is an uninteresting one. But the notation
“($x, y, …) etc.” is just such a norm. It is a straight
translation of a norm of our word-language, the expression “there is …”, which
is a form of expression into which countless grammatical forms are squeezed.’
‘A question that suggests itself is this: must we
introduce the cardinal numbers in connection with the notation ($x,
y, …) . fx.
fy
… ? –
there is no ‘must’ involved here –
it depends on what you have in mind and why
‘Is the calculus of the cardinal numbers somehow
bound up with the calculus of the signs ($x, y, …) . fx.
fy
… ?’ –
is firstly to ask – can cardinality – the sign-game
that is cardinality – be played in this calculus?
yes – of course
is it ‘bound up’ with the calculus of the signs – ($x,
y, …) . fx.
fy
…?
cardinality –
is not ‘bound by’ any notation
we play the game cardinality –– in whatever context
we find suitable – with whatever notation we are using
‘Is that kind of calculus perhaps in the nature of
things the only application of cardinal numbers?’ –
it’s ‘application’ – as with any game – is the
setting – in which it is played –
therefore – you can say cardinality has no
application – or that it has whatever application it has
‘We might put our question in this way too: in the
propositions of our language – if we imagine them translated into Russell’s
notation – do the cardinal numbers always occur after the sign “$”?
This question is closely connected with another: Is a numeral always used in
language as a characterization of a concept – of a function? The answer to that
is that our language does always use the numerals as attributes of
concept-words – but that these concept-words belong to different grammatical
systems that are so totally distinct from each other (as you see from the fact
that some of them have meaning in contexts in which others are senseless), that
a norm making them all concept-words is an uninteresting one. But the notation
“($x,
y, …) etc.” is just such a norm. It is a
straight translation of a norm of our word-language, the expression “there is
…”, which is a form of expression into which countless grammatical forms are
squeezed.’ –
yes – you can see it this way –
but you could also argue that ‘there is’ – is in
fact a logical space – the carving
out of a logical space – that is empty – and thus allows for any description –
and yes – the description – ‘concept-words’ – would
fit there as indeed would any other characterization – any other description of
the terms or signs used – in any language-game or any language use
the notation “($x, y, …) etc.” – is simply a description – of a
starting point in language use –
it is a formal characterization – not of any actual
language use – but rather of the ground of propositional action –
it is a characterization of the domain of the
proposal – of the proposition –
otherwise it is just an instance of an artificial
language – set up to serve a philosophical cause – or objective –
Russell’s logical analysis is inventive and of
interest – but the overall objective of providing a foundation to language – to
thought – is fool’s gold
the proposition is a proposal – open to question –
open to doubt – uncertain
all we do in any so called ‘analysis’ – is explore
uncertainty
‘If we disregard functions containing “=” (x = a . v . x = b) etc. ), then on Russell’s
theory 5 =1 if there are no functions satisfied by only one argument, or by only 5 arguments. Of course at first this
proposition seems nonsensical; for in that case how can one sensibly say that
there are no such functions? Russell would have to say that the statement that
there are five functions and the statement that these are one-functions can
only be separated if we have in our symbolism a five class and a one class.
Perhaps he could say that his view is correct because without the paradigm of
the class 5 in the symbolism, I can’t say at all that a function is satisfied
by five arguments. That is to say, from the existence of the sentence “($j) : (E1 x) . jx”
its truth already follows. – So you seem to be able to say: look at this
sentence, and you will see that it is true.’ And in a sense irrelevant for our
purposes that is indeed possible: think of the wall of a room on which is
written in red “in this room there is something red”. – ’
the point is we can use whatever symbolism suits
our purpose –
and as Wittgenstein points out in relation to
Russell’s logic – there is – there will be questions whatever language-game is
being played
as for – ‘look at this sentence, and you see that
it is true’ –
look at that sentence and you see a game
‘This problem is concerned with the fact that in an
ostensive definition I do not state anything about the paradigm (sample); I
only use it to make a statement. It belongs to the symbolism and is not one of
the objects to which I apply the symbolism.
For instance, suppose that “1 foot” were defined as
the length of a particular rod in my room, so that instead of saying “this door
is 6 ft high” I would say “this door is six times as high as this length”
(pointing to the unit rod). In that case we wouldn’t say things like “the
proposition ‘there is an object whose length is 1 ft’ proves itself,
because I couldn’t express the proposition at all
if there were no object of that length”. (That is, if I introduced the sign “this length” instead of “1 foot”, then
the statement that the unit rod is 1 foot long would mean “this rod has this
length” (where I point both times to the same rod). Similarly one cannot say of
a group of strokes serving as a paradigm of 3, that it consists of 3 strokes.
“If the proposition isn’t true, then the
proposition doesn’t exist” means: “if the proposition doesn’t exist, then it
doesn’t exist”. And one proposition can never describe the paradigm in another,
unless it ceases to be a paradigm. If the length of the unit rod can be
described by assigning it the length “1 foot”, then it isn’t a paradigm of the
unit length; if it were, every statement of length would have to be made by
means of it.’
an object to which I apply the symbolism is – by
that symbolism – made known
in the absence of any application of any symbolism
– ‘the object’ – if you can even call it that – is unknown
the object does not belong to the symbolism – the object is made – made known – by the
symbolism
‘In that case we wouldn’t say things like “the
proposition ‘there is an object whose length is 1 ft’ proves itself, because I
couldn’t express the proposition at all if there were no object of that
length”.’ –
let’s be clear here the proposition – is a proposal
–
there is no ‘proving itself’ –
as a proposal – it is open to question – open to
doubt – it is uncertain
it is not that I couldn’t express the proposition
at all if there were no object of that length –
the proposition could well be advanced –
and if it was – in the absence of an object of that
length – the proposal – would be open to question – open to doubt –
as indeed it would be – in the presence of an
object of that length
‘Similarly one cannot say of a group of strokes
serving as a paradigm of 3, that it consists of 3 strokes.’
you can
say this – and as with any proposal – any proposition – it is open to question
a proposal – a proposition – is logically speaking
– an argument place
“If the proposition isn’t true, then the
proposition doesn’t exist” means: “if the proposition doesn’t exist, then it
doesn’t exist”. And one proposition can never describe the paradigm in another,
unless it ceases to be a paradigm. If the length of the unit rod can be
described by assigning it the length “1 foot”, then it isn’t a paradigm of the
unit length; if it were, every statement of length would have to be made by means
of it.’
‘if the proposition isn’t true’ –
is only to say – if the proposal is not affirmed –
if the proposal is put – the proposition exists
this so called ‘paradigm’ – is a proposal – is a
description – open to question – open to doubt – uncertain
and of course one proposition can describe another
proposition –
if we are to elucidate a proposal (‘paradigm’) – we
propose in relation to it
if the suggestion is that this ‘paradigm’ is in
some way beyond description – or hidden in a proposition
that is just essentialist and obscurantist nonsense
‘1 foot’ is a description of length –
open to question – open to doubt –
uncertain
‘If we give any sense at all to a proposition of
the form “~ ($j) : (E x) . jx”
it must be a proposition like: “there is no circle on this surface containing
only one black speck” (I mean: it
must have that sort of determined
sense, and not remain vague as it did in Russellian logic and in my own Tractatus).
If it follows from the propositions
r) ~ ($j) : (E x) . jx
and s) ~ ($j) : (E x, y) . jx
. jy
that 1 =2, then here “1” and “2” don’t mean what we
commonly mean by them, because in word-language the propositions r
and s
would be ‘there is no function that is
satisfied by only one thing” and ‘there is no function that is satisfied by
only two things.” And according to the rules of our language these are
propositions with different senses.
One is tempted to say: “In order to express ‘($x,
y) . jx
. jy’
we need 2 signs ‘x’ and ‘y’.” But that has no meaning. What we need for it, it
is, perhaps, pen and paper; and the proposition means no more than “to express
‘p’ we need ‘p’.” ’
‘it must be a proposition like: “there is no circle
on this surface containing only one
black speck” (I mean: it must have that sort of determined sense, and not remain vague as it did in Russellian
logic and in my own Tractatus).’ –
the proposition “~ ($j) : (E x) . jx”
– is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
what Wittgenstein mistakes for vagueness – is
propositional uncertainty –
no proposal – however constructed – is beyond
question – beyond doubt –
if you are looking for ‘certainty’ – go for
rhetoric – prejudice and ignorance –
‘And according to the rules of our language these
are propositions with different senses.’ –
look the sense of any proposition is never settled
–
our propositions are uncertain – and move in
uncertainty –
we explore uncertainty – and we create forms with
it and in it
‘to express ‘p’ we need ‘p’ ’ –
the proposition is a proposal – if it’s put – it’s
put – if it’s not – it’s not
‘to express ‘p’ we need ‘p’ ’ –
is just another proposal – and relative to any
proposition actually advanced –
of no significance or relevance whatsoever –
perhaps that is Wittgenstein’s point?
‘If we ask: but what then does “5 + 7 = 12” mean –
what kind of significance or point is left for this expression after the
elimination of the tautologies, etc. from the arithmetical calculus? The answer
is: this equation is a replacement rule which is based on certain general
replacement rules, the rules of addition. The content of 5 + 7 = 12 (supposing
someone did know it) is precisely what children find difficult when they are
learning the proposition in arithmetic lessons.’
‘supposing someone did know it’ – a joke from Dr.
Wittgenstein?
what we have here with 5 + 7 = 12 – is a sign-game
–
its ‘content’ – is the symbolism –
its content is just what you see
and as Wittgenstein says –
‘this equation is a replacement rule which is based
on certain general replacement rules, the rules of addition’ –
this practise has developed – and developed –
because human beings find it useful –
why? – because they do
‘No investigation of concepts, only insight into
the number-calculus can tell us that
3 + 2 = 5. That is what makes us rebel against the
idea that
“(E 3x) . jx
. (E 2
x) . yx
. Ind.: É . ( E
5x) . jx v yx”
could be the proposition 3 + 2 = 5. For what
enables us to tell that this expression is a tautology cannot itself be the
result of an examination of concepts, but must be recognisable from the
calculus. For the grammar is a calculus. That is, nothing of what the tautology
calculus contains apart from the number calculus serves to justify it and if it
is number we are interested in the rest is mere decoration.
Children learn in school that 2 x 2 = 4, but not
that 2 = 2’
3 + 2 = 5 –
yes you can rewrite it as –
“(E 3x) . jx
. (E 2
x) . yx
. Ind.: É . ( E
5x) . jx v yx”
and you describe the statement as a ‘tautology’ –
which however you then explain – comes back to –
3 + 2 = 5
so –
‘nothing of what the tautology calculus contains
apart from the number calculus serves to justify it and if it is number we are
interested in the rest is mere decoration’
I would say – rather than ‘decoration’ – rhetoric –
which if you don’t take a hard-arse line – amounts to the same thing
what this is about – and what Wittgenstein doesn’t
actually get to is that understanding 3 + 2 = 5 is recognizing a game –
and that is seeing that a ‘game’ – is a rule governed proposition – a rule
governed propositional activity
we recognize this in all manner of language uses –
and we do it quite naturally
and as for 2 = 2 –
2 = 2 – is no profound and final logical analysis –
it is rather a perfect example of (logical) rhetoric
–
a stupid attempt to provide foundation were there
is none – and in fact – where there is no need for there to be any
it is rather a statement of the blinding obvious –
a statement entirely unnecessary to make
and a statement any child would see as pointless
20. Statements
of number within mathematics
‘What distinguishes a statement of number about a
concept from one about a variable? The first is a proposition about the
concept, the second a grammatical rule concerning the variable.
But can’t I specify a variable by saying that its
values are to be objects satisfying a certain function? In that way I do not
indeed specify the variable unless I know which objects satisfy the function,
that is, if these objects are given me in another way (say by a list); and then
giving the function becomes superfluous. If we do not know whether an object
satisfies the function, then we do not know whether it is to be a value of the
variable, and the grammar of the variable is in that case simply not expressed
in this respect.”
‘What distinguishes a statement of number about a
concept from one about a variable? The first is a proposition about the
concept, the second a grammatical rule concerning the variable.’ –
a proposition about a concept – is a proposition
about a proposition –
a proposal in relation to a proposal
a grammatical rule concerning the variable –
is logically speaking a proposal regarding a
proposal –
the variable is formally undefined –
the concept – not so –
though any definition of a concept –
is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
the logic of the concept and the variable – is at
base – the same –
the difference has to do with propositional space
or location
a concept is located – even though this ‘location’
is – and always will be open to question
the variable on the other hand – is open –
it’s location in propositional space in respect to
any formal action – is irrelevant –
in fact strictly speaking – it has no location
here we are talking about different propositional
functions –
or different types of propositional functions
different uses that have come about in
propositional practice
‘But can’t I specify a variable by saying that its
values are to be objects satisfying a certain function? In that way I do not
indeed specify the variable unless I know which objects satisfy the function,
that is, if these objects are given me in another way (say by a list); and then
giving the function becomes superfluous.’
the ‘object’ – is a description of a point in propositional
space – a starting point –
the function – a description of action in
propositional space –
effectively different modes of the proposed
variable –
different descriptions – different perspectives –
different uses
‘If we do not know whether an object satisfies the
function, then we do not know whether it is to be a value of the variable, and
the grammar of the variable is in that case simply not expressed in this
respect.’ –
‘if we do not know’? –
what we do is propose
values for a variable –
and any proposal is just that – a proposal – open
to question – open to doubt – uncertain –
that is our ‘knowledge’ –
and as for the grammar –
grammar is an analysis of the proposal – an
interpretation –
and as with any interpretation of any kind –
uncertain in every respect –
nevertheless – whatever the interpretation – we
follow or invent –
that is what we proceed with
‘Statements of number in mathematics (e.g. “The equation x2 =
1 has two roots”) are therefore quite a different kind of thing from statements
of number outside of mathematics (“There are two apples on the table”).’
the statement ‘The equation x2
= 1 has two roots’ – refers to a rule governed propositional action
(equation) – a mathematical game
the statement ‘There are two apples
on the table’ refers to rule governed propositional action (addition) – a
mathematical game
there is no ‘in or out’ of
mathematics – if the propositional focus – in whatever context – is the
mathematical game
‘If we say AB admits of 2 permutations, it sounds
as if we had made a general assertion, analogous to “There are 2 men in the
room” in which nothing further is said or need to be known about the men. But
this isn’t so in the AB case, I cannot give a more general description of AB,
BA and so the proposition that no permutations are possible cannot say less
than that the permutations AB, BA are possible. To say that 6 permutations of 3
elements are possible cannot say less, i.e. anything more general, than is
shown by the schema:
A B C
A C B
B A C
B C A
C A B
C B A
For it is impossible
to know the number of possible permutations without knowing which they are.
And if this weren’t so, the theory of combinations wouldn’t be capable of
arriving at its general formulae. The law which we see in the formulation of
the permutations is represented by the equation p = n! In the same sense, I
believe as that in which the circle is given by its equation. – Of course I can
correlate the number 2 with permutations AB, BA just as I can 6 with the
complete permutations of A, B, C, but that does not give me the theorem of
combination theory. – What I see in AB, BA is an internal relation which
therefore cannot be described. That is, what
cannot be described is that which makes this class of permutations complete.
I can only count what is actually there, not possibilities. But I can e.g. work
out how many rows a man must write if in each row he puts permutations of 3
elements and goes on until he cannot go further without repetition. And this
means, he needs 6 rows to write down the permutations ABC, ACB, etc., since
these just are “the permutations of A, B, C”. But it makes no sense to say that
these are all permutations of A B C.’
‘For it is impossible
to know the number of possible permutations without knowing which they are’
–
yes you have to play the permutations / calculation
game – to see – to know – what the number of permutations is
‘What I see in AB, BA is an internal relation which
therefore cannot be described. That is, what
cannot be described is that which makes this class of permutations
complete. I can only count what is actually there, not possibilities.’ –
what I see in AB, BA is an internal relation which
therefore cannot be described? –
‘internal relation’ if it’s something you ‘see’ –
is something that can be described –
‘internal relations’ – is a description
and i.e. –
to say ‘AB, BA are the 2 permutations admitted by AB’ – is another description
AB, BA – can be described – in any number of ways
to say ‘x cannot be described’ – is to describe
with – ‘x’ –
what is – is what is described –
or you could say here – to be – is to be described
if you are in the business of not describing – don’t describe – be silent –
‘what
cannot be described is that which makes this class of permutations
complete. I can only count what is actually there, not possibilities.’ –
I can play the permutations game – the calculation
game – in whatever context given e.g. AB or ABC –
that’s all this is about
‘We could imagine a combination computer exactly
like the Russian abacus’
yes
‘It is clear that there is a mathematical question:
“How many permutations of –
say 4 elements are there?”, a question of precisely
the same kind as “What is 25 x 18?”. For in both cases there is a general
method of solution.
But still it is only with respect to this method
that this question exists.’
both questions are game questions –
and the game is calculation –
the questions will likely make no sense to you –
unless you see them as game questions – and you know how to play these games –
that is to say –
you understand rule governed propositional play
‘The proposition that there are 6 permutations of 3
elements is identical with the permutations schema and thus there isn’t here a
proposition “There are 7 permutations of 3 elements”, for no such schema
corresponds to it.’
a permutations schema is a description of game
moves –
there are 7 permutations of 3 elements – is not a
description of a game –
a game that is played
‘You could also conceive the number 6 in this case
as another kind of number, the permutations-number of A B C. Permutation is
another kind of counting.’
6 is a number in a number game – in whatever
context you play the counting game
permutations – is not ‘another kind of counting’ –
‘permutations’ is a propositional context – in
which the counting game is played
‘permutations’ – is a game description
‘If you want to know what a proposition means, you
can always ask “How do I know that?” Do I know that there are 6 permutations of
3 elements in the same way in which I know that there are 6 people in this
room? No. Therefore the first proposition is of a different kind from second.’
the right question is – do I know how to play the
calculation game – in relation to the question of permutations? –
and can I play the calculation in the context of
the people in this room?
there is no difference in kind between the first question and the second –
both questions are game-propositions –
and the game is calculation –
the only difference is context – is setting – where you do the calculation –
that is to say – in what descriptive setting –
you play the game
‘You may also say that the proposition “There are 6
permutations of 3 elements” is related to the proposition “There are 6 people
in this room” in precisely the same way as “3 + 3 = 6”, which you could also
cast in the form “There are 6 units in 3 + 3”. And just as in the one case I
can count the rows in the permutation schema, so in the other I can count the
strokes in
| | |
| | |
Just as I can prove that 4 x 3 = 12 by means of the
schema
o o o
o o o
o o o
I can also prove 3! = 6 by means of the permutation
schema.’
‘There are 6 permutations of 3 elements’ and ‘There
are 6 people in this room’ are game propositions –
‘elements’ and ‘people in this room’ – are
calculation settings –
that is descriptive settings for the action of calculation
a permutations schema – is not ‘proof’ of anything
–
a permutations schema is an illustration – a model for the permutations / calculation game
there is no proof in game playing – there is just
the game – and its play
‘The proposition “the
relation R links two objects”, if it is the same as “R is a two place relation,
is a proposition of grammar.
the proposition – the proposal – ‘the relation R links two
objects’ – is – a description of – a propositional form –
if applied to a proposition
– it is an analysis of the
proposition –
it tells you what ‘R’ is –
and how to use it
‘R is a two place relation’
–
a description of how ‘R’ –
is used in a particular (formal logic) context of use –
again a direction even – as
to how to interpret ‘R’
Wittgenstein hypothesizes
here –
all very well – to propose
a view of these propositions – of their relationship
and yes – the propositions can be understood in Wittgenstein’s
sense of ‘a proposition of grammar’ –
this being said however –
all you have here from Wittgenstein – is a proposal – open to question – open
to doubt
logically speaking –
uncertain
21. Sameness
of number and sameness of length
‘How should we regard the propositions “these hats
are of the same size”, or “these rods have the same length” or “these patches
have the same colour”? Should we write them in the form “($L).La
.Lb”? But if that is intended in the usual way, and so is used with the usual
rules, it would mean that it made sense to write “($L).La”,
i.e. “the patch has a colour”, “the rod has a length”. Of course I can write “($L).La
.Lb” for “a and b have the same length” provided that I know and bear in mind
that “($L).La”
is senseless; but then the notation becomes misleading and confusing (“to have
a length”, “to have a father”). – What we have here is something that we often
express in ordinary language as follows: “If a has the length L, so does b”;
but here the sentence “a has the length L” has no sense, or at least not as a
statement about a: the proposition should be reworded “if we call the length of
a ‘L’, then the length of b is L” and ‘L’ is essentially a variable.’
what is clear here is that the formal
representation does not deal with ‘same’ –
formal representation does not provide successful
analysis
and analysis here – when you strip away the
philosophical pretension of the logicists –
is no more than – duplication
and once analysis is seen for just what it is – you
have to ask – successful or not –
what is the point – why bother?
‘The proposition incidentally has the form of an
example, of a proposition that could serve as an example for the general sentence:
we might go on: “for example, if the length of a is 5 metres, then the length
of b is 5 metres, etc.” – “Saying “the rods a and b have the same length” say
nothing about the length of each rod; for it doesn’t even say “that each of the
two has a length”. So it is quite unlike “A and B have the same father” and
“the name of the father of A and B is ‘N’”, where I simply substitute the
proper name for the general description. It is not that there is a certain
length of which we are at first only told that a and b both possess it, and of
which ‘5m’ is the name. If the lengths are lengths in the visual field we can
say the two lengths are the same, without in general being able to “name” them
with number. –The written form of the proposition “if L is the length of a, the
length of b too is L” is derived from the form of an example. And we might
express the general proposition by actually enumerating examples and adding
“etc.”. And if I say “a and b are the same length; if the length of a is L,
then the length of b is L; if a is 5m long then b is 5 m long, if a is 7 m
long, then b is 7 m long, etc.”, I am repeating the same proposition. The third
formulation shows that the “and” in the proposition doesn’t stand between the
two forms, as it does in “($x).
jx.
yx”,
where one can also write “($x).
jx”
and “($x).
yx”.’
the proposition has the form of an example?
well prime facie – it doesn’t
yes you can reinterpret it that way –
but if it is to be ‘an example’ – it is in effect a
different proposition
still the question is – does such a
reinterpretation account for ‘same’?
enumerating examples – as such – doesn’t do it
enumeration of examples might well function as a
proposal in a game of syntactical correspondence between two or more proposals
–
but in that case enumeration is a means to the end
–
not the end itself
‘Let us take as an example the proposition “there
are the same number of apples in each of the two boxes”. If we write this
proposition in the form “there is a number that is the number of the apples in
each of the boxes” here too we cannot construct the form “there is a number
that is the number of apples in this box” or “the apples in this box have a
number”. If I write: ($x).
jx.
~ ($x,
y). jx
. jy.
=. $n Ix). j I, etc. then we might write
the proposition “the number of apples in both boxes is the same as “($n).
jn.
yn”.
But “($n).
jn”
would not be a proposition.’
yes – once again the formal representation is not
up to it
‘there is a number that is the number of apples in
each box’
clearly is not an adequate representation of ‘there
are the same number of apples in each of the two boxes’
the clearest way of putting it is this –
we have two propositions – (1) ‘there are 5 apples
in this box’ – (2) ‘there are 5 apples in that box’
the proposal ‘there is the same number of apples in
each box’ – relates the two proposals – and is in effect shorthand for the two
proposals
the ‘number’ – whatever it is – is the result of an
arithmetical game of addition
the real point of
‘there is the same number of apples in each of the two boxes’ – is that
the arithmetical game has been applied to the two proposals
‘The expressions “same number”, “same length”,
“same colour”, etc. have grammars which are similar but not the same. In each
case it is tempting to regard the proposition as an endless logical sum whose
terms have the form jn.yn.
Moreover, each of these words has several different meanings, i.e. can itself
be replaced by several words with different grammars. For “same number” does
not mean the same when applied to lines simultaneously present in the visual
field as in connection with the apples in two boxes; and “same length” applied
in visual space is different from “same length” in Euclidean space; and the
meaning of “same colour” depends on the criterion we adopt for sameness of
colour.’
any ‘expression’ – in any propositional form – is
open to question – open to doubt – is logically uncertain –
and yes – in each case (‘same number’ –‘same
length’ – ‘same colour’) – you could regard
the proposition as an endless logical sum –
and as pointed out each of these words can have
different meanings – different grammars
it all depends on where you are propositionally –
and what you are doing propositionally
formal representation is just one propositional
option – and one that I think has a very narrow application
to expect one propositional form to function in all
contexts of use is really a failure to understand propositional reality
this ‘logical analysis’ enterprise – is wrongheaded
–
at best it’s a harmless language game –
at worst – a pretentious waste of time
‘If we are talking about patches in the visual
field seen simultaneously, the expression “same length” varies in meaning
depending on whether the lines are immediately adjacent or at a distance from
each other. In word-language we often get out of the difficulty by using the
expression “it looks”.’
it’s not a ‘difficulty’ – the real world of
propositional reality – just is that a proposal – in any language use – is open to question – open to doubt – is
uncertain –
we live in uncertainty – we deal with uncertainty –
language is the expression of uncertainty
the idea – put most stridently by Russell – that
you can via some formal construction – some formal language – eliminate propositional
uncertainty – should be seen for what it is – the attempt to defy and scuttle
propositional reality
to present such an idea as ‘logical’ – is to my
mind – the gravest form of deception –
any such endeavour is an undermining of logical
reality – and nothing more than rhetoric – to the service of ignorance and base
prejudice
‘Sameness of number, when it a matter of a number
of lines “that one can take in at a glance” is a different sameness from that
which can only be established by counting the lines.’
here we are talking about a hunch – a guess –
as distinct from a propositional game based on
calculation
‘We want to say that the equality of length in
Euclidean space consists in both lines measuring the same cm, both 5 cm, both
10 cm etc; but where it is a case of two lines in visual space being equally
long; there is no L that both lines have.
One wants to say: two rods must always have the
same length or different lengths. But what does that mean? What it is, of
course, is a rule about modes of expression. “There must either be the same
number or a different number of apples in the two boxes.” The method whereby I
discover whether two lines are of the same length is supposed to be the laying
of a ruler against each line: but do they have the same length when the rulers
are not applied? In that case we
would say we don’t know whether during that time the two lines have the same or
different lengths. But we might also say that during that time they have no
length, or perhaps no numerical length.’
if there is no L that both lines have –
how can it be also said that they are ‘equally
long’?
the real point here is – if there is no L that both
lines have –
all that means is –
there has been no measurement taken –
or no measurement can be taken
‘do they have the same length when the rulers are
not applied? –
we don’t know
‘we might also say that during that time they have
no length, or perhaps no numerical length’ –
yes – the point being that length is a function of
measurement – which is a calculation
calculation is a propositional game –
if you don’t play the game –
obviously – there can be no result
‘Something similar, if not exactly the same holds,
holds of sameness between numbers.’
yes – there are no numbers outside of a
counting-game
‘When we cannot immediately see the number of dots
in a group, we can sometimes keep the group in view as a whole while we count,
so that it makes sense to say it hasn’t altered during the counting. It is
different when we have a group of bodies or patches that we cannot keep in a
single view while we count them, so that we don’t have the same criterion for
the group’s not changing while it is counted.’
we do ‘see’ the dots in a group – but we haven’t
counted them
we assume
that the group hasn’t altered during the counting –
and as with any assumption – this assumption is –
open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
you might say ‘there may have been a change that
was not observed’ –
nevertheless in the absence of an observable change
– we assume no change – and play the
counting-game
what we have with a ‘single view’ – is a context –
where we have bodies or patches that we cannot keep
in a single view – we have a different propositional context –
I think the criterion for not changing is the same
– if we don’t see or recognize a change – then we assume that there is no
change
the assumption that there is no change underlies
the counting-game –
if there is a change – we have to start again –
if everything is changing – how can you count?
so – ‘that there is no change’ – is a
methodological assumption –
it is if you like a meta-game assumption
‘Russell’s definition of sameness of number is
unsatisfactory for various reasons. The truth is that in mathematics we don’t
need any such definition of sameness of number. He puts the cart before the
horse.
What seduces us into accepting the Russellian or
Fregean explanation is the thought that two classes of objects (apples in two
boxes) have the same number if they can be correlated 1 to 1. We imagine
correlation as a check of sameness of number. And here we do distinguish in
thought between being correlated and being connected by a relation; and
correlation becomes something that is related to connection as the “geometrical
straight line” is related to a real line, namely a kind of ideal connection
that is as it were sketched in advance by Logic so that reality only has to
trace it. It is possibility conceived as a shadowy actuality. This in turn is
connected with the idea of ($x).
jx
as an expression of the possibility of jx.’
it is not that Russell puts the cart before the
horse –
there is no cart
first up –
it is not two classes of objects (apples in two
boxes)
what we deal with is two proposals –
‘x number of apples in this box’ and ‘x
number of apples in that box’ –
two proposals – two propositions
and these propositions are different
correlation?
different propositions –
there is no 1 to 1 correlation here
as to the same number of apples –
what you have –
is an arithmetical game (addition) applied to the
two propositions –
and with the statement the ‘same number of apples
in each box’ –
you have a representation of that application
‘Logic’ – is not ‘an ideal connection sketched out
in advance’ –
‘Logic’ – is propositional reality
and that reality is that the proposition – the
proposal – is open to question – open to doubt – is uncertain
‘Logic’ – propositional activity – is the
exploration of propositional uncertainty
our propositional reality – is uncertain –
game playing as I see it – is relief from propositional reality
the game is rule-governed propositional behaviour
the very point of the ‘rule’ is that it is not
questioned – not doubted –
any rule – as with any proposition – any proposal –
can be questioned of course –
but the very point of the game is that it is
not
if you don’t want to play – don’t play –
if you would prefer to question – knock yourself
out –
we think and we play – that’s the sum of it
‘We can regard the concept of sameness of number in
such a way that it makes no sense to attribute sameness of number or its
opposite to two groups of points except in the case of two series of which one
is correlated 1 to 1 to at least a part of the other. Between such series all we
can talk about is unilateral or mutual inclination. This has really no more
connection with particular numbers than equality or inequality of length in the
visual field has with numerical measurement. We can, but need not, connect it with numbers. If we connect it with
the number series, then the relation of mutual inclusion or equality of length
between the rows becomes a relation of sameness of numbers. But then it isn’t
only that y5
follows from II. j5.
We also have II following from j5. y5. That means that here S = II.’
as to sameness of number –
really ‘sameness of number’ – is a propositional
game–
which is to say a game where syntactical
correspondence is proposed –
that is a correspondence between symbols – in a mathematical game – or in two or more mathematical games
there is no mystery to this
No comments:
Post a Comment